The Basic Problems of Phenomenology

Overview

A lecture course that Martin Heidegger gave in 1927, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology continues and extends explorations begun in Being and Time. In this text, Heidegger provides the general outline of his thinking about the fundamental problems of philosophy, which he treats by means of phenomenology, and which he defines and explains as the basic problem of ontology.

Indiana University Press

"In Albert Hofstadter's excellent translation, we can listen in as ...

See more details below
Paperback (Revised Edition)
$23.45
BN.com price
(Save 16%)$28.00 List Price

Pick Up In Store

Reserve and pick up in 60 minutes at your local store

Other sellers (Paperback)
  • All (20) from $15.27   
  • New (13) from $18.34   
  • Used (7) from $15.27   
Sending request ...

Overview

A lecture course that Martin Heidegger gave in 1927, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology continues and extends explorations begun in Being and Time. In this text, Heidegger provides the general outline of his thinking about the fundamental problems of philosophy, which he treats by means of phenomenology, and which he defines and explains as the basic problem of ontology.

Indiana University Press

"In Albert Hofstadter's excellent translation, we can listen in as Heidegger clearly and patiently explains...the ontological difference."--Hubert L. Dreyfus, Times Literary Supplement

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Times Literary Supplement

"In Albert Hofstadter’s excellent translation, we can listen in as Heidegger clearly and patiently explains... the ontological difference." —Times Literary Supplement

Religious Studies Review

"This volume belongs in every collection on Heidegger and is required reading for anyone interested in this major thinker." —Religious Studies Review

Teaching Philosophy

"For all students and scholars, Basic Problems will provide the "missing link" between Husserl and Heidegger, between phenomenology and Being and Time." —Teaching Philosophy

Key Reporter

"Perhaps the most generally accessible text that Heidegger published.... The translation is superb." —Key Reporter

From the Publisher
"This volume belongs in every collection on Heidegger and is required reading for anyone interested in this major thinker." —Religious Studies Review

"Perhaps the most generally accessible text that Heidegger published.... The translation is superb." —Key Reporter

Read More Show Less

Product Details

Meet the Author

Albert Hofstadter is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz. His translation of Heidegger's Poetry, Language, Thought received a National Book Award.

Indiana University Press

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

The Basic Problems of Phenomenology


By Martin Heidegger, Albert Hofstadter

Indiana University Press

Copyright © 1982 Indiana University Press
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-253-20478-3



CHAPTER 1

Kant's Thesis: Being Is Not a Real Predicate


§7. The content of the Kantian thesis

Kant discusses his thesis that being is not a real predicate in two places. One is a small essay, Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes [The sole possible argument for a demonstration of God's existence] (1763). This work belongs to Kant's so-called pre-critical period, the period before the Critique of Pure Reason (1781). It falls into three parts. Our thesis is dealt with in the first part, which discusses the basic questions and divides into four considerations: (1) "On existence in general"; (2) "On inner possibility insofar as it presupposes an existence"; (3) "On absolutely necessary existence"; (4) "Argument for a demonstration of God's existence."

Kant discusses the thesis again in his Critique of Pure Reason (first edition, A, 1781; second edition, B, 1787), specifically in the "Transcendental Logic." Our citations will henceforth be from the second edition (B). "Transcendental logic," or, as we may also say, the ontology of nature, falls into two parts: "transcendental analytic" and "transcendental dialectic." In the transcendental dialectic, book 2, chapter 3, section 4 (B 620 ff), Kant again takes up the thesis he discusses in the Beweisgrund essay. The section is entitled "The Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God."

In both places, in the Beweisgrund and in the Critique, the thesis is treated in the same way. For the purpose of our exposition, in which we propose to examine this thesis in detail, we shall refer to both these works. We may cite them briefly as Beweisgrund and Critique, references to the former being made according to Ernst Cassirer's edition of Kant's works. Before we elucidate the content of the Kantian thesis, let us characterize briefly the pertinent essentials of the context in which it is discussed in both places.

First of all, however, a general terminological observation is required. As the title of the Beweisgrund indicates, Kant is speaking of the proof of the existence of God. He speaks similarly of the existence of things outside us, of the existence of nature. This concept of existence, Dasein, corresponds in Kant to the Scholastic term existentia. Kant therefore often uses the expression "Existenz," "actuality" ["Wirklichkeit"], instead of "Dasein." In contrast, our own terminological usage is a different one, which, as will appear, is grounded in the nature of the case. For what Kant calls existence, using either Dasein or Existenz, and what Scholasticism calls existentia, we employ the terms "Vorhandensein," "being-extant," "being-at-hand," or "Vorhandenheit," "extantness." These are all names for the way of being of natural things in the broadest sense. As our course proceeds, the choice of these expressions must itself be validated on the basis of the specific sense of this way of being—a way of being that demands these expressions: things extant, extantness, being-at-hand. In his terminology Husserl follows Kant and thus utilizes the concept of existence, Dasein, in the sense of being extant. For us, in contrast, the word "Dasein" does not designate, as it does for Kant, the way of being of natural things. It does not designate a way of being at all, but rather a specific being which we ourselves are, the human Dasein. We are at every moment a Dasein. This being, the Dasein, like every other being, has a specific way of being. To this way of the Dasein's being we assign the term "Existenz," "existence"; and it should be noted here that existence or the expression "the Dasein exists" is not the sole determination of the mode of being belonging to us. We shall become acquainted with a threefold determination of this kind, which is of course rooted in a specific sense in existence. For Kant and Scholasticism existence is the way of being of natural things, whereas for us, on the contrary, it is the way of being of Dasein. Therefore, we might, for example, say "A body does not exist; it is, rather, extant." In contrast, Daseins, we ourselves, are not extant; Dasein exists. But the Dasein and bodies as respectively existent or extant at each time are. Accordingly, not every being is an extant entity, but also not everything which is not an extant entity is therefore also a nonbeing or something that is not. Rather, it can exist or, as we have yet to see, subsist or have some other mode of being.

The Kantian or the Scholastic concept of reality must be sharply distinguished from the Kantian concept of existence in the sense of presence-at-hand as a way of being of things and from our own terminology of extantness. In Kant as well as in Scholasticism, which he follows, the expression "reality" does not mean what is commonly understood today by the concept of reality in speaking, for example, about the reality of the external world. In contemporary usage reality is tantamount to actuality or existence in the sense of extantness, presence-at-hand. The Kantian concept of reality is altogether different, as we shall see. Understanding the thesis that being is not a real predicate depends on understanding this Kantian concept of reality.

Before beginning the interpretation of this thesis, it will be worthwhile to characterize briefly the pertinent context in which it appears. This context strikes the eye on reading the title of the work first mentioned as well as the heading of the relevant section of the Critique of Pure Reason. It deals with the proof of the existence, actuality, and—in our terms—extantness of God. We are confronted by the striking fact that Kant discusses the most general of all the concepts of being where he is dealing with the knowability of a wholly determinate, distinctive being, namely, God. But, to anyone who knows the history of philosophy (ontology), this fact is so little surprising that it rather just makes clear how directly Kant stands in the great tradition of ancient and Scholastic ontology. God is the supreme being, summum ens, the most perfect being, ens perfectissimum. What most perfectly is, is obviously most suited to be the exemplary being, from which the idea of being can be read off. God is not merely the basic ontological example of the being of a being; he is at the same time the primal ground of all beings. The being of the non-divine, created entity must be understood by way of the being of the supreme being. Therefore it is no accident that the science of being is oriented in a distinctive sense toward the being which is God. This goes so far that Aristotle already called prote philosophia, first philosophy, by the name of theologia. We should take note here that this concept of theology has nothing to do with the present-day concept of Christian theology as a positive science. They have only the name in common. This orientation of ontology toward the idea of God came to have a decisive significance for the subsequent history of ontology and for ontology's destiny. It is not our present concern to deal here with the legitimacy of this orientation. It is enough that there is nothing surprising about the fact that Kant discussed the concept of being or existence in the context of the possibility of our knowledge of God. More precisely, what Kant was occupied with was the possibility of that proof of the existence of God which he was the first to call the ontological proof. There comes to light here a remarkable phenomenon which we shall repeatedly encounter in philosophy before Kant and also in post-Kantian philosophy, and in its most extreme form in Hegel, namely, that the problem of being in general is most closely bound up with the problem of God, the problem of defining his essence and demonstrating his existence. We cannot here discuss the reason for this remarkable connection, which nevertheless is in the first instance not at all a mere matter of course, for that would require us to discuss the foundations of ancient philosophy and metaphysics. The fact persists even in Kant and it proves, quite externally to begin with, that Kant's mode of inquiry still proceeds wholly within the channel of traditional metaphysics. In the places mentioned Kant deals with the possibility of the ontological proof. A peculiar feature of this proof is that it tries to infer God's existence from his concept. The philosophical science which in Kant's opinion starts purely from concepts and tries dogmatically to settle something about that which is, is ontology or, in traditional language, metaphysics. That is why Kant calls this proof from the concept of God the ontological proof, where "ontological" is equivalent in signification to dogmatical, metaphysical. Kant does not himself deny the possibility of metaphysics but is in search precisely of a scientific metaphysics, a scientific ontology, the idea of which he defines as a system of transcendental philosophy.

The ontological proof is old. It is commonly traced back to Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109). Anselm proposed his proof in a short treatise, Proslogium sen alloquium de Dei existentia [Proslogium, or discourse on the existence of God]. In chapter 3, "Proslogium de Dei existentia," the real core of the proof is presented. In the literature this proof is frequently called the Scholastic proof of God's existence. The term is inappropriate because in many cases it was precisely medieval Scholasticism which challenged the logical validity and cogency of this proof. It was not Kant but Thomas Aquinas who first contested the logical validity of this proof, whereas Bonaventura and Duns Scotus admit the proof. But the Kantian refutation of the possibility of the ontological proof is much more radical and thoroughgoing than that given by Thomas.

The characteristic feature of this proof is the attempt to infer God's existence from his concept. The determination that God is the most perfect being, ens perfectissimum, belongs to his concept, the idea of him. The most perfect being is the one that can lack no possible positive characteristic and that possesses every positive characteristic in an infinitely perfect way. It is impossible that the most perfect being, such as we think God to be in our concept of him, should not have any given positive characteristic. In conformity with the concept of it, every defect is excluded from this being. Therefore also, manifestly, or even before all else, that it is, its existence, belongs to the perfection of the most perfect being. God is not what he is, in accordance with his essential nature as the most perfect being, unless he exists. That God exists thus follows from the concept of God. The proof declares: If God is thought according to his essence, that is to say, according to his concept, then his existence must be thought along with it. This readily suggests the question, Does it follow therefrom that we must think God as existing, think his existence? We cannot here go into the provenance of this proof, which reaches back beyond Anselm to Boethius and Dionysius the Areopagite, and thus to Neoplatonism; nor can we examine the various modifications it has undergone and the attitudes that have been taken toward it in the history of philosophy. We shall only in passing describe the view of Thomas Aquinas because it is suitable as a background against which to bring the Kantian refutation into sharpest outline.

Thomas Aquinas discusses and criticizes the possibility of the ontological proof of God's existence, which he does not yet call by this name, in four places: (1) the Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Sentences 1, dist. 3, qu. 1, art. 2 ad 4; (2) Summa theologica 1, qu. 2, art. 1; (3) Summa contra gentiles 1, chaps. 10–11; (4) De veritate, qu. 10, art. 12. The last mentioned is the most lucid of these accounts. In this place Thomas raises the question utrum deum esse sit per se notum menti humanae, sicut prima principia demonstrationis, quae non possunt cogitari non esse; "whether God is known to the human intellect by himself and in himself like the first principles of demonstration [the law of identity, the law of contradiction], which cannot be thought as not being." Thomas asks: Do we know about God's existence with the aid of God's concept, according to which he cannot not exist? In section 10 we read: Ad hoc autem quod sit per se notum, oportet quod nobis sit cognita ratio subjecti in qua concluditur praedicatum. In Thomas' discussion, too, something like a predicate appears, just as it does in the Kantian thesis that being is not a real predicate. "For something to be known in itself, to be intelligible of itself, nothing else is required save that the predicate which is asserted of the being in question is de ratione subjecti, from the concept of the subject." Ratio is equivalent in meaning to essentia or natura or, as we shall see, reality. In this case the subject cannot be thought without that which appears in the predicate. But in order for us to have such a cognition, which Kant later called an analytic cognition, that is to say, in order for us to be able to infer a thing's characteristics immediately from its essence, it is necessary that the ratio subjecti, the concept of the thing, should be known to us. For the proof of God's existence this implies that the concept of God, his whole essence, must be discernible to us. Sed quia quidditas Dei non est nobis not a, ideo quoad nos Deum esse non est per se notum, sed indiget demonstratione. Ideo nobis necessarium est, ad hoc cognoscendum, demonstrationes habere ex effectibus sumptas. But since the quidditas, what God is, his whatness, his essence, is not known to us, since with respect to us God is not transparent in his essence, but requires proof based on the experience of what he has created, therefore, the demonstration of God's existence from his concept lacks adequate grounding of the starting-point of the proof, namely, the concept.

According to Thomas the ontological proof is impossible because, starting out from ourselves, we are not in a position to expound the pure concept of God so as to demonstrate from it the necessity of his existence. We shall see that it is at a different place that Kant tackles the ontological proof critically, attacks its real nerve, and thus first really unhinges it.

In order to discern more clearly this place in the ontological proof on which the Kantian criticism makes its assault, we shall give to this proof the formal shape of a syllogism.

Major premise: God, by his concept, is the most perfect being.

Minor premise: Existence belongs to the concept of the most perfect being.

Conclusion: Therefore God exists.


Now Kant does not dispute that by his concept God is the most perfect being, nor does he contest the existence of God. With regard to the form of the syllogism, this means that Kant leaves undisturbed the major premise and the conclusion. If he nevertheless attacks the proof, the attack can bear only upon the minor premise, which says that existence belongs to the concept of the most perfect being. The thesis of Kant, whose phenomenological interpretation we are taking as our theme, is nothing but the fundamental denial of the possibility of the assertion laid down in the minor premise of the ontological proof. Kant's thesis that being or existence is not a real predicate does not assert merely that existence cannot belong to the concept of the most perfect being or that we cannot know it to belong to that concept (Thomas). It goes further. It says, fundamentally, that something like existence does not belong to the determinateness of a concept at all.

We must first show how Kant argues for his thesis. In this way it will become clear of itself how he explicates the concept of existence, in our sense of extantness.

The first section of the Beweisgrund divides into four disquisitions, the first of which is "On existence in general." It discusses three theses or questions: (1) "Existence is not a predicate or determination of any thing at all"; (2) "Existence is the absolute position of a thing and thereby differs from any sort of predicate, which, as such, is posited at each time merely relatively to another thing"; (3) "Can I really say that there is more in existence than in mere possibility?"

The first proposition, "Existence is not a predicate or determination of any thing at all," is a negative characterization of the nature of existence. The second proposition gives a positive definition of the ontological sense of existence—existence equals absolute position. The question enunciated in the third place takes a stand toward a contemporary explication of the concept of existence, such as was given by Wolff or his school, according to which existence signifies complementum possibilitatis: the actuality of a thing, or its existence, is the complement of its possibility.


(Continues...)

Excerpted from The Basic Problems of Phenomenology by Martin Heidegger, Albert Hofstadter. Copyright © 1982 Indiana University Press. Excerpted by permission of Indiana University Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Translator’s Preface
Translator’s Introduction

Introduction
1. Exposition and General Division of the theme
2. The concept of philosophy. Philosophy and world-view
3. Philosophy as science of being
4. The four theses about being and the basic problems of phenomenology
5. The character of ontological method. The three basic components of phenomenological method
6. Outline of the course

Part One: Critical Phenomenological Discussion of Some Traditional Theses about Being
Chapter One: Kant’s Thesis: Being Is Not a Real Predicate
7. The content of the Kantian thesis
8. Phenomenological analysis of the explanation of the concept of being or of existence given by Kant
9. Demonstration of the need for a more fundamental formulation of the problem of the thesis and of a more radical foundation of this problem

Chapter Two: The Thesis of Medeval Ontology Derived from Aristotle: To the Constitution of the Being of a Being There Belong Essence and Existence
10. The Content of the thesis and its traditional discussion
11. Phenomenological clarification of the problem underlying the second thesis
12. Proof of the inadequate foundation of the traditional treatment of the problem

Chapter Three: The Thesis of Modern Ontology: The Basic Ways of Being Are the Being of Nature (res Extensa) and the Being of Mind (Res Cogitans)
13. Characterization of the ontological distinction between res extensa and res cogitans with the aid of the Kantian formulation of the problem
14. Phenomenological critique of the Kantian solution and demonstration of the need to pose the question in fundamental principle
15. The fundamental problem of the multiplicity of ways of being and of the unity of the concept of being in general

Chapter Four: The Thesis of Logic: Every Being, Regardless of Its Particular Way of Being, Can Be Addressed and Talked About by Means of the "Is". The Being of the Copula
16. Delineation of the ontological problem of the copula with reference to some characteristic arguments in the course of the histroy of logic
17. Being as copula and the phenomenological problem of assertion
18. Assertional truth, the idea of truth in general, and its relation to the concept of being

Part Two:
The Fundamental Ontological Question of the Meaning of Being in General
The Basic Structures and Basic Ways of Being
Chapter One: The Problem of the Ontological Difference
19. Time and temporality
20. temporality [Zeitlichkeit] and Temporality [Temporalitat]
21. Temporality [Temporalitat] and being
22. Being and beings. The ontological difference

Editor’s Epilogue
Translator’s Appendix: A Note on the Da and the Dasein
Lexicon

Indiana University Press

Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)