Contesting Democracy: Political Ideas in Twentieth-Century Europe / Edition 1

Hardcover (Print)
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $36.80
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 18%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (9) from $36.80   
  • New (2) from $131.06   
  • Used (7) from $36.80   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing 1 – 1 of 2
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$131.06
Seller since 2008

Feedback rating:

(191)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
0300113218 New. Looks like an interesting title!

Ships from: Naperville, IL

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing 1 – 1 of 2
Close
Sort by

Overview

This book is the first major account of political thought in twentieth-century Europe, both West and East, to appear since the end of the Cold War. Skillfully blending intellectual, political, and cultural history, Jan-Werner Müller elucidates the ideas that shaped the period of ideological extremes before 1945 and the liberalization of West European politics after the Second World War. He also offers vivid portraits of famous as well as unjustly forgotten political thinkers and the movements and institutions they inspired.
Müller pays particular attention to ideas advanced to justify fascism and how they relate to the special kind of liberal democracy that was created in postwar Western Europe. He also explains the impact of the 1960s and neoliberalism, ending with a critical assessment of today's self-consciously post-ideological age.

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Financial Times - Tony Barber
" [An] impressive survey of 20th-century European political thought.”—Tony Barber, Financial Times
Timothy Garton Ash
'This is a pathbreaking study in the intellectual history of Europe in our time. Analysing ideas that had political impact, Jan-Werner Mülller illuminates a never-ending debate about true and false democracy.' - Timothy Garton Ash
Mark Lilla
'Ideology is the place where theory and practice, philosophy and history, meet. Understand this "in-between" and you are well on your way to understanding the deepest dynamics that shape modern political existence. In this illuminating study Jan-Werner Müller helps us see the experience of twentieth-century Europe, East and West, in a fresh light by showing how its characteristic ideologies developed, functioned, and adapted to the world they created. By focusing on "political thought that matters politically" Müller takes us beyond the simple stories we have inherited about revolution and reaction, post-war reconstruction, the Cold War, the Sixties, and much else. By the end he puts us in a much better position to understand the forces at work in contemporary European politics and the strange attraction of the "anti-political" ideology that governs our time.' - Mark Lilla, author of The Reckless Mind: Intellectuals in Politics
Charles Maier
'The great achievement of Jan Werner Müller's Contesting Democracy is to guide us safely across the vast unruly manifestos of European political ideas, from the appalling doctrines that helped generate the totalitarian regimes and world wars to the uneasy decency of our own era, without sacrificing the reader's sense of urgency and signifiance.' - Charles S. Maier
John P. McCormick
'Jan-Werner Müller’s Contesting Democracy is the most philosophically sophisticated and topically comprehensive study of political ideas in twentieth- century Europe yet available. It exhibits a masterful command of primary texts, archival sources, and myriad secondary literatures. Müller assembles for political theorists, intellectual historians and social scientists previously disparate pieces of intellectual-political life from the last, most incomprehensible century on that eternally perplexed and infinitely perplexing continent. By so expertly conveying the full significance of communism, fascism, liberalism, social democracy and Christian democracy, Müller makes the European twentieth century much more fathomable from a historical, moral and political standpoint than any previous work, in any language.' - John P. McCormick, author of Machiavellian Democracy
The New Statesman - David Marquand
“…… [A] fine study of the impact of mass democracy on European political cultures.”—David Marquand, The New Statesman
Standpoint Magazine - Jeremy Jennings
“…..[An] excellent book…..Müller provides an insightful and comprehensive overview of the development of political ideas in 20th-century Europe that takes in Fascism, Communism, social democracy, liberalism, and much else.—Jeremy Jennings, Standpoint Magazine
Times Higher Education - Roger Morgan
“Muller’s profound and stimulating book has much to offer, both to specialists and for others.”—Roger Morgan, Times Higher Education
International Affairs - Vladimir Tismaneanu
“There is no chapter of the twentieth century’s European political thought that is not luminously analysed in this superbly written, lucidly argued and immensely engaging book.”—Vladimir Tismaneanu, International Affairs
European Review of History
"Jan-Werner Muller has written a fine book which for the first time gives us a reliable synthesis of twentieth-century European political thought." European Review of History
Springer - A. Craiutu
"The originality of Contesting Democracy stems in good part from the diversity of its subject, its well thought-out structure, and, last but not least, its lively anecdotes and memorable quotes. Müller writes elegantly and has a good eye for important ideas and neglected authors." A. Craiutu,Springer.
J�rgen Habermas

'The most innovative parts of this admirably thorough and comprehensive book deal with the not so liberal roots of the liberal political institutions and practices that came to fruition in post-war Europe. What strikes me is the balanced treatment of developments in Western and Eastern Europe.' - Jürgen Habermas
Jürgen Habermas

'The most innovative parts of this admirably thorough and comprehensive book deal with the not so liberal roots of the liberal political institutions and practices that came to fruition in post-war Europe. What strikes me is the balanced treatment of developments in Western and Eastern Europe.' - Jürgen Habermas
Jorgen Habermas
'The most innovative parts of this admirably thorough and comprehensive book deal with the not so liberal roots of the liberal political institutions and practices that came to fruition in post-war Europe. What strikes me is the balanced treatment of developments in Western and Eastern Europe.' - Jürgen Habermas
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780300113211
  • Publisher: Yale University Press
  • Publication date: 8/23/2011
  • Edition description: First Edition
  • Edition number: 1
  • Pages: 304
  • Product dimensions: 6.40 (w) x 9.30 (h) x 1.20 (d)

Meet the Author

Jan-Werner Müller teaches politics at Princeton University. His previous books include A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought and Another Country: German Intellectuals, Unification, and National Identity, both published by Yale University Press.

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

CONTESTING DEMOCRACY

POLITICAL IDEAS IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY EUROPE
By JAN-WERNER MÜLLER

YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 2011 Yale University
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-300-18090-9


Chapter One

The Molten Mass

The whole state of society is more or less molten and you can stamp upon that molten mass almost anything as long as you do it with firmness and determination.

David Lloyd George, 1917

Today, the state enjoys its beatification. We turn to it almost blindly in sure faith that its way spells salvation.

Harold Laski, 1917

Today the relation between the state and violence is an especially intimate one.

Max Weber, 1919

Nowadays, a sure sign of the power of democratic ideology is the fact that so many people pretend to accept it. A sure sign of the decadence of aristocratic ideology is that it has no hypocritical defenders at all.

Vilfredo Pareto, 1920

The only meaning I can see in the word 'people' is 'mixture'; if you substitute for the word 'people' the words 'number' and 'mixture', you will get some very odd terms ... 'the sovereign mixture', 'the will of the mixture', etc.

Paul Valéry

At Christmas 1918 Max Weber had recently returned from Berlin to Munich, only to find himself in the midst of a 'bloody carnival'. In the capital he had played a prominent role in deliberations about a new German constitution. This was somewhat surprising: for almost twenty years, the Heidelberg professor had suffered from various illnesses and was hardly seen in public. In the last two years of the First World War, however, he had written a series of polemical articles and tried desperately to act as a political educator of the German nation. He had also hoped to stand for the constitutional assembly and, eventually, parliament. But it was clear now that the liberal party with which he had associated himself would always nominate more professional politicians, and not someone widely considered an irascible academic. Weber could not have had high hopes either that the constitution drafters would follow any of his recommendations.

A few months earlier, Weber had been asked by a student society at Munich University whether he would deliver a lecture on 'Politics as a Vocation' for them, in a series where he had already given one talk on 'Academia as a Vocation' in 1917. Weber had been reluctant, but apparently, when he learnt that the students were considering Kurt Eisner as an alternative, he agreed. Eisner, a freelance journalist and life-long socialist, had declared a republic in Bavaria on 8 November 1918, even before the German Kaiser had abdicated in Berlin – and thereby precipitated what Weber was to call the 'bloody carnival' of revolution. He had only contempt for a character like Eisner: in Weber's estimation the man was a littérateur dabbling in politics, a demagogue in love with his own rhetoric, but also the victim of his very short-term success – which, in Weber's view, the head of the Bavarian council republic mistook for genuinely political success when it was merely literary: rather than Eisner actually projecting authority (or just power), romantic hopes for redemption through politics were projected on to a man who, after all, was just a hack.

Weber held that there were three bases of legitimating rule: there was tradition, where men and women obeyed on the basis of precedent; there were formal legal procedures, so that law was judged to be legitimate if it had passed through the correct channels and could be executed by bureaucrats sine ira et studio; and, finally, there was personal charisma, which had an affinity with revolutionary politics. The latter term had originated in the sphere of religion and initially designated the qualities of prophets: 'it is written ... but I say unto you'. According to Weber, it could be applied generally to leaders who seemed to have been graced with special gifts and who therefore inspired fervent devotion and deep trust among their followers. Eisner, Weber thought, was this last type, and a dangerous variety. And so rather than have the self-declared head of the new Bavarian Volksstaat seduce the students with his high-flying socialist dreams, he would offer some hard-won lessons in political realism.

On 28 January 1919 Weber began what would turn out to be the most famous single lecture in the history of political thought: 'Politik als Beruf ', with 'Beruf ' referring to both profession and a sense of personal calling. Weber did not exactly start off on a high note:

This lecture ... will necessarily disappoint you ... You will instinctively expect me to take a position on problems of the moment. But that will be the case only in a purely formal way ... when I shall raise certain questions concerning the significance of political activity in the whole conduct of life. In today's lecture, all questions that refer to which policy ... one should adopt must be eliminated. For such questions have nothing to do with our general question ...

What was this 'general question'? In Weber's lecture it was: what is politics as a profession or a vocation? But, more broadly speaking, the question was how possible were responsible political action and stable liberal regimes in what Weber called a disenchanted world, a world in which religion, metaphysics and other sources of meaning – especially collective meaning – seemed all to have been placed in doubt. Weber was convinced that traditional legitimacy – based on precedent and prescription – was disappearing, and that Europeans had entered the democratic age for good. The charisma of monarchs – not so much a personal quality as what Weber called 'the charisma of blood', passed down from one generation to the next, but also attaching to the institution itself – had been dispelled by the disasters of a war during which monarchs had generally revealed themselves as incompetent. What had also disappeared was the belief that members of different nationalities and religions could live peacefully together in one political association like the Habsburg Empire, watched over by a revered Kaiser in whom his subjects felt some genuine trust. Weber was sure that democracy could be realized only within homogeneous nation-states. And there was no way back from democracy now. In Weber's mind, disenchantment and democracy went together; they were both peculiar to the path of development that the West had taken. Dealing with them responsibly posed the greatest political challenge to Europeans in the first decades of the twentieth century.

The Age of Security (for Some)

To understand how European political thought developed in the twentieth century, it helps to understand how it had developed in the nineteenth – and which of its underlying assumptions no longer seemed credible in the period after the First World War. Weber had been shaped by the high tide of nineteenth-century liberalism, and what the Austrian writer Stefan Zweig in retrospect called 'the golden Age of Security' (which, he added, had also been the golden age of insurance policies). Writing from the vantage point of exile in Brazil in 1942 (and about to take his own life), Zweig remembered that in those pre-war years 'everything radical, everything violent seemed impossible in an age of reason'. People of his generation, those who had been young before the First World War, had felt an incomparable optimism and trust in the world, a world which they thought was well on the way to ever more freedom as well as 'true cosmopolitanism'.

This age of reason and security had rested on three central ideas (or sometimes just moral intuitions) which had solidified in particular political and economic institutions. Security had meant, to begin with, the absence of war and other kinds of large-scale violence (at least when seen from Vienna or somewhere else safely removed from the Balkans, to say nothing of the world outside Europe). Fewer Europeans died in combat in the nineteenth century than in the eighteenth; and the period 1871 to 1914 proved to be the longest stretch of intra-European peace up to that point in history (the most obvious exception, when the rest of the globe is taken into account, was Great Britain – which was almost always at war somewhere).

Security in the sense of international peace was not thought to be just a lucky break for Europeans; it seemed to be connected to the increasing interdependence of European states and empires through the circulation of money, goods – and people. The decades before the First World War saw what has sometimes been called a 'first wave of globalization'. The Manchester Guardian announced that 'space has been eliminated' and that 'frontiers no longer exist'. It was a golden age of internationalism in the sense of free trade, international co-operation in setting standards and pooling sovereignty for economic benefits: there was, for instance, the European Postal Union, the Scandinavian and Latin monetary unions; above all, there was the gold standard linking all major currencies. But there was also a sense – and a reality – of freedom of movement and consequently large waves of migration. As Zweig's contemporary Felix Somary, a banker born in fin-de-siècle Vienna, pointed out: 'all barriers, as well as the words "hostage" and "exile", seemed to us to belong to a distant age which had long been overcome'. Travel seemed easy; in fact, in the late nineteenth century, only Turkey and Russia had passport controls, and they regulated internal movement only (in the eyes of many observers, it was not an accident that, along with Montenegro, these were the only countries which, by 1900, still had no parliaments). The German industrialist and politician Walther Rathenau observed in 1912 that never before had the European peoples been so close to each other, visited each other so much and known each other so well.

Freedom of movement was just one aspect of a general liberal belief in increasing liberty for everyone, especially if that term primarily meant 'freedom from the state'. As the British historian A. J. P. Taylor was to put it, until August 1914 'a sensible, law-abiding Englishman could pass through life and hardly notice the existence of the state, beyond the post office and the policeman'. Citizens could live where they liked; they needed neither identity cards nor passports; and, not least, they could buy foreign currency (and goods) to their hearts' content. John Maynard Keynes added that the Englishman 'regarded this state of affairs as normal, certain, and permanent, and any deviation from it as aberrant, scandalous and avoidable'. And he went on: 'The projects and politics of militarism and imperialism, of racial and cultural rivalries ... were little more than the amusements of his daily newspaper, and appeared to exercise almost no influence at all on the daily course of social and economic life, the internationalization of which was nearly complete in practice.'

The freedom for things and people to move across borders and the self-determination of societies were not seen by European liberals as incompatible. As has often been pointed out, up until the First World War there existed a by and large unbroken belief in progress, especially scientific progress; what has been less noticed was an equally firm and fundamental belief among liberals that individual and collective self-determination could go together harmoniously.

But 'collective self-determination' had a very limited meaning: the state, if it played any major role at all, was to be at the service of society; and society in turn could best express what it needed and wanted in parliaments run by gentlemen with a sense of the common good: the Age of Security was also the Age of Parliamentarism. To be sure, only those parts of society could express themselves which actually had the vote – and, in most European countries, suffrage remained heavily restricted. Liberals assumed that over time more and more people would qualify for it through education and property; those without either could not be trusted with choosing governments, as they were likely to destroy the very foundations on which the Age of Security rested. Full democratization thus always remained a theoretical possibility for liberals, though one likely to be far off in the future.

But not everybody wanted to wait until liberals deemed the people to be rich or well read enough to participate in politics. Across Europe the late nineteenth century and the early twentieth century saw a series of struggles over the franchise and the nature of political representation. Women demanded the vote, first with peaceful demonstrations, then with attacks on property, then with attacks on themselves, that is to say hunger strikes. The vote was to be uncoupled from income; an officially unequal power distribution like Prussia's three-tier system – which made political power depend on the capacity to pay taxes – seemed increasingly scandalous. Ethnic groups wanted their say in the large multinational empires. And ruling elites with hereditary political privileges came under attack – as in the epic battles over the role of the House of Lords in Britain, which resulted in the aristocrats' disempowerment in 1911.

Both liberal and conservative elites thought they could master what increasingly looked like a comprehensive crisis in representation – in terms both of who was represented and of what kinds of political claims could be made and reconciled within the political system as it was. Italy proved a paradigmatic example: the liberals there gambled that they could slowly extend the franchise and yet contain social conflict through the strategy of trasformismo: drawing ever more groups into the system by making them share some power – while, more importantly, rewarding them with spoils (and inducing them to moderate their claims). So they gave the vote to peasants by removing literacy requirements, betting that the peasants would stay politically quiescent or at least controllable. As Giovanni Giolitti, a liberal and past-master of trasformismo (and in fact originator of the word), explained in 1901: 'No one should deceive himself into thinking that the lower classes can be prevented from acquiring their share of economic and political influence. The friends of existing institutions have one duty above all: it is persuading these lower classes, with facts, that they have more to hope from existing institutions than from any dreams of the future.' This kind of transformation by co-optation had little to do with anything like responsible cabinet government through a cohesive Liberal Party in the way it became consolidated in Britain, for example – in fact, there was no Italian liberal party, just a collection of soi-disant liberal notables, until the early 1920s.

In practice, extending the franchise and empowering parliaments did not proceed in a neat parallel. And neither did the professionalization of parliaments. While legislatures in general were becoming more effective in controlling executives, they were not necessarily populated by ever more specialized politicians. Indeed countries on the European periphery were nominally governed by liberal legislatures, but de facto controlled by notables and gentlemen-administrators who built ad hoc coalitions to get themselves elected – and, as in Italy, used their local power to keep newly enfranchised groups under control. Nonetheless, while discontent with the kind of democracy on offer in even the most advanced European countries simmered, there remained a sense that claims for participation would be addressed in an orderly and peaceful way; they did not fundamentally seem to threaten the Age of Security.

In addition to hopes for continuing peace and progress, there was a third intuition underlying the age: what one might call a belief in the eventual Europeanization of the world, in the sense of European dominance of the world and global acceptance of Europe's civilization as a model. Europeans, or so it was assumed, ruled other parts of the world for their own good, not for the benefit of the 'old continent'. As the French writer Paul Valéry put it: 'Wherever that [European] Mind prevails, there we witness ... the maximum of labor, capital, and production, the maximum of ambition and power, the maximum transformation of external Nature, and the maximum of relations and exchanges.' This unashamed superiority complex of what Valéry called Homo europaeus could persist not least because others were always ready to acknowledge Europe's pre-eminence. As William James lamented, 'it seems the natural thing for us to listen whilst the Europeans talk. The contrary habit, of talking while the European listens, we have not yet acquired.'

(Continues...)



Excerpted from CONTESTING DEMOCRACY by JAN-WERNER MÜLLER Copyright © 2011 by Yale University. Excerpted by permission of YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Contents

List of Illustrations....................ix
Introduction....................1
1 The Molten Mass....................7
2 Interwar Experiments: Making Peoples, Remaking Souls....................49
3 Fascist Subjects: The Total State and Volksgemeinschaft....................91
4 Reconstruction Thought: Self-Disciplined Democracies, 'People's Democracies'....................125
5 The New Time of Contestation: Towards a Fatherless Society....................171
6 Antipolitics, and the Sense of an Ending....................202
Notes....................243
Index....................273
Acknowledgements....................279
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)