Darwinism and its Discontents

Hardcover (Print)
Buy New
Buy New from BN.com
$51.90
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $1.99
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 96%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (36) from $1.99   
  • New (8) from $41.37   
  • Used (28) from $1.99   

Overview

This book presents an ardent defense of Charles Darwin's theory of evolution against its many critics by one of the leading experts on this subject. Offering a clear and comprehensive exposition of the thinking of Darwin, Michael Ruse brings the story up to date, examining important issues such as the origins of life, the fossil record, the mechanism of natural selection, and rival theories such as punctuated equilibrium, the story of human evolution (including the recently found "hobbits," Homo floresiensis), fraud in biological science, literary approaches to evolution, and the philosophical and religious implications of Darwinism, notably a discussion of Creationism and its modern day offshoot, Intelligent Design Theory. Ruse draws upon the most recent discoveries, but writes with a minimum of jargon.
Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Publishers Weekly
Ruse, a well-known evolutionary historian and philosopher, defends Darwin from all comers, whether religious critics; those who, like Gertrude Himmelfarb, have accused Darwin of being a second-rate scientist; or postmodernist critics who say science is a social construction and not objective truth. Ruse (Can a Darwinian Be a Christian?) expounds on why he accepts evolution as fact. Though he doesn't buy the argument that all science is merely a social construct, he acknowledges that Darwinism holds a mirror up to the times and reflects contemporary thinking, and he looks at the forms Darwinism has taken in philosophy, literature and popular culture. Some readers may think that Ruse, who freely and frequently admits that he isn't a Christian, doesn't quite provide a level playing field on which to confront some of his intellectual opponents, in particular the Christian philosopher Alvin Plantinga and the atheist scientist Richard Dawkins. Still, Ruse's agnosticism keeps him from being doctrinaire ("Perhaps there is a God on the other side... I do not know"). Some readers will struggle with Ruse's occasional philosophic density. Nevertheless, this should interest fans of the philosophy of science and readers caught up in the contemporary debate about evolution. (Aug.) Copyright 2006 Reed Business Information.
From the Publisher
"Anyone who wants to understand evolutionary theory and the fascinating issues that surround it, can find no better place than Michael Ruse's Darwinism and Its Discontents. He discusses the objections raised to evolutionary theory down through the most legitimate to those that are anything but legitimate. His discussions are fair, measured and informed. High school students, undergraduates and the public at large would find this book worth reading."
-David Hull, Northwestern University

"Of all the literally hundreds of books out there that claim to have the true, right or only line on Darwin, Ruse has the beating of them all. He shows the wonder in both the natural world and Darwin's efforts to understand it."
-Allan C. Hutchinson, Toronto Globe and Mail

"Darwinism and Its Discontents is vintage Ruse: clear, incisive, focused on fundamental and controversial topics, written with verve. Michael Ruse is a philosopher, comfortably at home with the biology, and sensitive to the religious controversies."
-Fancisco J. Ayala, University of California, Irvine

"Ruse is unique in his combined knowledge of evolutionary principles, history of science, philosophy, and theology, and he brings them all to bear with clarity and effect in evaluating the present-day status of evolutionary thought."
-Edward O. Wilson, Harvard University

"The enemies of a thorough-going Darwinism are many: fundamentalists who think it a damnable doctrine; social-constructionists who would drain away its blood; and even some evolutionary biologists who balk at taking the last step. Over the years, Michael Ruse has engaged them all with scholarship, intelligence, and wit—his most potent weapon. Now in a more synthetic mode, Darwinism and Its Discontents brilliantly marshals these instruments to disarm the recalcitrant and convince the fair minded. The book displays a humane thinker who yet flexes muscle and moxie."
-Robert J. Richards, University of Chicago

"Ruse, a well-known evolutionary historian and philosopher, defends Darwin from all comers, whether religious critics; those who have accused Darwin of being a second-rate scientist; or postmodernist critics who say science is a social construction and not objective truth...this should interest fans of the philosophy of science and readers caught up in the contemporary debate about evolution."
-Publishers Weekly

"Darwinism and Its Discontents is Ruse's most comprehensive look at Darwinism to date...He negotiates the terrains of history, philosophy, and theology well enough to offer cogent versions of the central issues and their multiple sides...For an introduction to the mainstream Darwinian view and its wider context, one might not find a better entrée than Ruse's account."
-Horace L. Fairlamb, University of Houston-Victoria, symploke

"Ruse is a skilled writer able to present the most intricate details of evolutionary theory in an understandable way. He is more than well-informed...this book offers a good selection and a relatively fair picture of standard criticisms of Darwinism...It should be read by anyone wishing to be introduced to or reminded of the 'state of the art' of the 'Darwin wars'. —Tomislav Bracanovic, University of Zagreb: Philosophy in Review

Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780521829472
  • Publisher: Cambridge University Press
  • Publication date: 8/28/2006
  • Pages: 326
  • Product dimensions: 5.98 (w) x 8.98 (h) x 0.98 (d)

Meet the Author

Michael Ruse is one of the world's leading authorities on the history and philosophy of Darwinian evolutionary theory. He is the author of many books; his most recent book with Cambridge University Press is The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology (2007) with David L. Hull. A Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada and of the American Association for the Advancement of Science, he has been a Herbert Spencer Lecturer at Oxford University and a Gifford Lecturer at Glasgow University, and he has also held Guggenheim and Isaak Walton Killiam fellowships.

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt


Cambridge University Press
052182947X - Darwinism and its discontents - by Michael Ruse
Excerpt

Introduction

If I were to give an award for the single best idea anyone has ever had, I’d give it to Darwin, ahead of Newton and Einstein and everyone else. In a single stroke, the idea of evolution by natural selection unifies the realm of life, meaning, and purpose with the realm of space and time, cause and effect, mechanism and physical law.

D. C. Dennett (1995)

This is the judgment of the philosopher Daniel Dennett about the English naturalist Charles Robert Darwin, who discovered the theory of evolution through natural selection, published in 1859 in his Origin of Species, the work that provides the ongoing framework for evolutionary studies today. It is a judgment with which I concur. Many do not. Most obviously, there are the many American evangelical Christians who take the words of the Bible absolutely literally and who hence assert that the world and its denizens were created by God, miraculously, some six thousand years ago, in the space of a week. Recently, these “Creationists” have been joined by believers of a more sophisticated ilk, the so-called Intelligent Design theorists, who argue that no natural account of origins can be adequate, and hence that all histories must make space for special interventions by some form of thinking being. These are people at one end of the religious spectrum, yet eventhose toward the other end – those who argue that Genesis must be interpreted metaphorically and that God did create according to laws of evolution – tend nevertheless to suppose that blind laws need help, that they need special pushes, to create the wonderful world of life and to alleviate the harshness of the Darwinian process.

   It is easy and natural for those of us of a more secular bent to smile somewhat smugly at what we take to be the insecurities and failings of the religious. We do not reject evolution, even for humans, and we want no interventions from outside nature. But interestingly and depressingly, when it comes to Darwinism – natural selection as the chief causal process behind all organisms – large numbers of people stand virtually back to back with the religious critics. It is well known now that many students of literature and (particularly) those drawn to cultural studies have little but contempt for (and, one suspects, fear of ) almost everything to do with science and technology. Notorious is their claim that there is no objective truth and that everything – science particularly – is a social construction, an epiphenomenon of the society in which it is produced. A scientific theory tells us no more about reality than does a political manifesto or a preacher’s sermon. In this gloomy assessment, Darwinian evolutionary theory always has a special place – right at the center of the pit of damnation reserved for the very worst sinners. Supposedly, Darwinism reflects and justifies the grossest sins in our society – domination, greed, selfishness, sexism, and more. Those who have tried to portray Darwinism positively in literature must be tarred with the same brush. In the opinion of the many historians who espouse this ideology of science, all of this is hardly a surprise. Apart from the fraud and plagiarism that would make the most hardened internet-essay buyer blush, the coming of Darwinism was more an excuse for various people in the nineteenth century to park their prejudices in a respectable place, and this is a practice that has continued down to the present.

   Many members of the social sciences – particularly in areas like sociology and cultural anthropology – feel much the same way. The very suggestion that humans might be animals, reflecting their biology like other brutes, is enough to bring on apoplexy in the nicest and best-qualified assistant professors. If not that, then firmly shut mouths and minds as tenure decisions loom. Darwinism supposedly leads straight to “genetic determinism” and other horrible philosophies that still have the odor of the vile world systems of the first part of the twentieth century. At the other end of the scientific spectrum, we now have physicists who tell us that their science can do it all for us – that there is no real need of natural selection. The laws of physics, unaided, can produce and explain everything worth knowing about organisms. Even the new areas of inquiry, like cognitive science, are getting into the act. People whose only knowledge of the living world has been filtered through the glow of the computer screen calmly tell us that their algorithms prove that the ideas of the Origin are now as outmoded as phlogiston theory and Ptolemaic astronomy.

   What is truly surprising is that this skepticism is to be found in the biological sciences, even in evolutionary studies. For the past three decades, there have been well-qualified and articulate evolutionary biologists who have been showing so visceral a hatred of Darwinian thinking that one suspects that their objections cannot be grounded purely in theory or evidence. Tempting as it is to indulge in psychoanalytic hypotheses about lack of self-worth, the reasons are probably more prosaic. The more noted critics are avowed Marxists – one book dedication runs “To Friedrich Engels, who got it wrong a lot of the time but got it right where it counted” – and this bastard offspring of Hegelian idealism, itself an attempt to rejuvenate the traditional religion of the centuries, is taken to be reason enough to abjure any theory that suggests that biology might make humankind at one with nature. The underlying themes of Christianity run deep and emerge in unexpected places. What turns all of this from farce to tragedy – especially for me, a professional philosopher – is that these critics, the evolutionists particularly, have infected my own field of study. For more than a quarter-century now, there has been an apparently limitless flow of philosophical invective directed against Darwinism. Even when it is temperate, it is almost uniformly negative or belittling.

   It is the nature of philosophy that its practitioners are drawn to attack received or standard positions – that is how we make our living, and there is no shame in that. But when you have a dominant scientific theory that its practitioners think is working magnificently well, and when one philosopher after another after another devotes large chunks of a career to proving that it is conceptually flawed and morally dubious, then one does start to wonder. It is all too reminiscent of those clever Jesuits who hauled Galileo over the coals for being a Copernican. Could it be that these most secular thinkers are a little scared that we humans might not be all that special after all? Can they not handle the awful truth that, after Darwin, the starting point of philosophical inquiry must be that we are the end product of a long, slow, natural process of selection rather than the creation of a good God miraculously on the Sixth Day? In the immortal words of Margaret Thatcher to George H. W. Bush when he showed signs of doubt and hesitation, when push comes to shove, are they getting a little wobbly? Thank goodness, there is yet time for repentance of sinners. Having spent a lifetime rejecting God and promoting Darwinism, the philosopher Anthony Flew has had a road-to-Damascus experience. Science cannot do it all. There must be something out there bigger than the both of us. “As people have certainly been influenced by me, I want to try and correct the enormous damage I may have done” (Wavell and Iredale 2004, 7).

   At the risk of damning myself in the eyes both of sound scholarship and of God, let me be categorical. All of the critics of Darwinism are deeply mistaken. Charles Darwin was a good scientist, the biological revolution of the nineteenth century led to genuine understanding, and today’s version of the theory is good quality science. It tells you important things about the real world. The integrity of evolutionists in general, and of Darwinians in particular, does not give great cause for complaint or alarm. It is of fundamental importance to philosophy to recognize the implications of Darwin’s work for the major questions of knowledge (epistemology) and morality (ethics). Life would be much poorer without creative writers, and one welcomes the fact that they turn their attention to evolution. Whether what they say about Darwinism is a cause for concern is another matter. Finally, although, like all good science, Darwinism challenges religion, Christianity specifically, it can and should provide a positive and creative stimulus for religious people to think about their faith and move forward in a richer and deeper way. But let me not spend time telling you about what I believe. Let me turn at once to telling you why I believe what I believe.





CHAPTER ONE

Charles Darwin and His Revolution

It is not to be expected of Darwin that he should have been troubled by thoughts of fallibility, relativity, or indeterminacy; but only that he should have observed the standards of his own time. And it was by those standards that he was in arrears. Nineteenth-century science was sufficiently aware of the desirability of precision and standardization to make Darwin’s tool chest seem distinctly unprofessional. In this, as in other respects, he gives the appearance of an amateur, an amateur even for his own day.

G. Himmelfarb (1959)

The above quotation is about Darwin as a practicing scientist and about how he went about things on a daily basis. It is typical of a certain strain of thought. At least here Darwin is only being labeled second-rate. His moral integrity is not being impugned. Others feel less constrained. Often we learn that Darwin’s supposed virtues were equally his vices: “a conservative outlook in every respect except the evolutionary hypothesis; a failure to recognize or to relate his own ideas, his larger ideas, with those of others working in the same field; and a flexible strategy which is not to be reconciled with even average intellectual integrity” (Darlington 1959, 60). No wonder the conclusion is that “Darwin was slippery.”

   These are judgments made nearly fifty years ago, and in the time since then a veritable Darwin industry has grown up, publishing hitherto-unseen documents, assessing and reassessing the personality and actions of Darwin and his fellows, and looking at broader issues (Ruse 1996a). But in some respects things are little better. One prominent scholar has made a whole career out of arguing that what we truly had was a “Non-Darwinian Revolution” (Bowler 1988, 2005). Others doubt that there was a revolution at all, and certainly do not think that it was truly Darwinian (Hodge 2005). It is argued that picking out one person, Charles Darwin, rather than any other is a matter of hero making after the event, and probably tells us more about our needs and interests than about anything that actually went on at the time (Secord 2000). There are others who agree that there was a revolution and that Darwin rode the crest of it, but (much as is suggested in the quotation above) who think that really Darwin was drawing on the efforts of others. The spade work was done for him (Herbert 2005; Lennox 2005). One variant of this line of approach is to suggest that although it is true that Darwin himself was English, it is a mistake to think that the Darwinian revolution was essentially English. Depending on the person writing, it is argued that the really important moves were made on the continent; France and Germany most commonly favored (Richards 2003; Corsi 2005).

   So what did happen and who does deserve the credit? Let us see.

The Problem of Final Causes

The earliest evolutionists, as we would understand them – thinkers proposing the idea or fact of evolution, namely, common origins for organisms, and believing that everything occurs according to normal laws of nature – were people like the general man of letters, the Frenchman Denis Diderot, writing in the middle of the eighteenth century. We must ask two questions. First, why did it take so long for such an idea to emerge? Second, why did it emerge exactly when it did? You might think that answers to both of these questions rest ultimately on empirical discoveries, and to a certain extent you would be right. Although the major focus of the Scientific Revolution that had begun two centuries earlier was on physics and later on chemistry, increasingly attention was directed to the life sciences broadly construed. The invention of the microscope stimulated interest in the world that exists beneath our vision; journeys of exploration brought back fabulous new finds of various life forms around the world; and this is not to mention the side effects of technology and the growing methods of industry – the fossil finds, for instance, thrown up by mining and by the labors involved in building roads and (increasingly) canals. But none of these findings really speaks right to our questions. Back at the time of the ancient Greeks, four or five centuries before Jesus, there were speculations of at least a quasi- or proto-evolutionary kind. Empedo- cles suggested that there were disembodied parts of organisms floating around, and that sometimes these came together, and that if they worked, they cohered and reproduced. Why did such an idea not take off back then? There was one major reason why such an idea did not convince. The serious thinkers – people like the philosophers Plato and Aristotle – simply could not see how the intricate functioning parts of organisms, what we now call “adaptations,” integrated into full living beings, could come about through blind, undirected law. The engineers call it Murphy’s Law: if things can go wrong, they will. Blind law leads to disorder and to mess, not to complex entities working toward ends (Ruse 2003).

   What then does lead to complexity working toward ends? The Greek philosophers had the answer: intelligence. Aristotle referred to the causes that bring on adaptive functioning as final causes (as opposed to things like efficient causes, which start things going), and for two thousand years it was these that made ideas of evolution simply not plausible. It was not old-fashioned prejudice but common sense. Where and what is the intelligence lying behind final causes? With the coming of Christianity, the great theologians – Saint Augustine and Saint Thomas Aquinas – argued that final causes point to the divine intelligence at the center of their religion. This yielded the so-called Argument from Design or Teleological Argument for the existence of God. “We see that things that lack intelligence, such as natural bodies, act for an end, and this is evident from their acting always, or nearly always, in the same way, so as to obtain the best result. Hence it is plain that not fortuitously, but designedly do they [things of this world] achieve their end.” From this premise, we move to the Creator behind things. “Now whatever lacks knowledge cannot move towards an end, unless it be directed by some being endowed with knowledge and intelligence; as the arrow is shot to its mark by the archer. Therefore some intelligent being exists by which all natural things are directed to their end; and this being we call God” (Aquinas 1952, 26–7).

   In the Scientific Revolution, the notion of final causes came under heavy attack in the physical sciences. They were judged scientifically useless and misleading. The philosopher Francis Bacon referred to them as akin to the Vestal Virgins – decorative but sterile. Yet in the biological areas of science, it was agreed that it is impossible to study nature without making reference to ends, to intentions, to values. “For there are some things in nature so curiously contrived, and so exquisitely fitted for certain operations and uses, that it seems little less than blindness in him, that acknowledges, with the Cartesians [the followers of the seventeenth-century French philosopher and mathematician René Descartes], a most wise Author of things, not to conclude, that, though they may have been designed for other (and perhaps higher) uses, yet they were designed for this use” (Boyle 1688, 397–8).

   This brings us to the eighteenth century, with people seeing that organisms need final causes for their explanation, and recognizing also that final causes seem inexplicable in purely natural terms. Evolution is a naturalistic explanation. Hence, evolution seemed an unreasonable position. Why then did evolutionary ideas start to emerge? Almost paradoxically, the reason lies in the Christian religion. As people started to find Christianity less and less compelling – as philosophers showed that it was unreasonable, as travelers brought back tales of other religions and other civilizations, as the move to an industrial world made the social force of the old beliefs less compelling and pertinent – they nevertheless sought alternatives in terms that Christianity had set. Although the Greeks had histories, they did not have a world history in our sense. They thought of the universe as eternal – going in endless cycles, with some limited variations here on Earth, but ultimately with no real direction. There was no creation out of nothing. Moreover, we humans were not the central focus of the action, however important we may seem to ourselves. Aristotle’s God spent his time contemplating his own perfection and had no interest in us. The Jewish story of origins, taken up into Christianity, changed all of that. We have a beginning, a middle, and talk of an end. We have the creation of life from nothing. We humans have a special status, because we are made in the image of God. The world does not necessarily exist just for us, but we are the star players. We have the story of our Fall, but then comes the drama of Jesus and his sacrifice on the Cross, creating the possibility of our salvation. We have our roles to play, worshiping God and loving our neighbors. And finally, if everything works out, assuming that God is on our side and we have done what we should, we have the promise of eternal life.

   People were looking for a non-Christian alternative, but set in the Christian terms – history, meaning, humans. Evolution told just such a story, offering rival answers to these same questions. It tells us where organisms came from – they started as primitive blobs way back when, and then grew and developed up to the forms that we have about us now. It puts us humans up at the front of the picture, as the most important organisms, that to which all has been pointing. It gives us tasks to do, namely, to keep things going and to make sure that things do not fall back – even better, to keep things moving forward. And finally, it offers hope of a brighter tomorrow, if not for us, then for our children and our children’s children.

   The reader today might question all of this – we ourselves will be questioning much before this book is finished. But for now, leave how you think that evolution should be interpreted, and go back nearly three hundred years to the way that the first evolutionists thought of the topic. Powerful at that time was a growing belief in the possibility and importance of progress – the idea that through our own efforts we humans ourselves can make life better and more efficient, in the realm of culture and technology. France particularly (but then spreading to other countries) was a home of such speculations. The idea’s greatest enthusiast, Jean-Antoine-Nicholas Caritat, marquis de Condorcet, saw progress as something that started with the new discoveries in science and the arts and medicine and so forth, arguing that they lead up from error and poverty and inequality, to truth and understanding and universal harmony. It was easy for a man like this to move from progress in the social world to progress in the biological world – from the simplest to the most complex, from the least valuable to the most valuable, from the monad to the man, as people were wont to say (Ruse 1996b, 2005b).

FIGURE 1.1 Ramon Lull’s ladder of ascent and descent of the mind (1305).

Image not available in HTML version

   This all tailored nicely with a notion (the so-called Chain of Being) going back to Aristotle that one can put all organisms in a line, from the simplest to the most complex – namely, us humans (Figure 1.1). Then, with a progressivist form of evolution postulated, the move was usually made in a circular fashion in justification back to the social world. Such were the speculations of Erasmus Darwin (1794–1796), grandfather of Charles, a physician writing in England toward the end of the eighteenth century. They were also the ideas – at the beginning of the nineteenth century – of the man who provided the fullest overall picture of upward natural change, the French (sometime aristocrat) Jean Baptiste de Lamarck (1809). He saw a “spontaneous generation” of lower life forms from mud and dirt, and then an upward progression through the Chain of Being, until we reach the human form. Admittedly, he thought that sometimes there are diversions and vagaries – generally brought on by the heritable effects of use and disuse, as the giraffe’s neck gets ever-longer through stretching to reach leaves on the upper branches of trees (the mechanism traditionally known as “Lamarckism”) – but, overall, nature shows the progress that Lamarck, as a good French radical, thought is evidenced in the best human societies. This does not mean that Diderot and Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck and other evolutionists (including, by the end of his long life, the German naturalist and poet Johann Wolfgang von Goethe) paid no attention to empirical facts. One aspect of the living world – noted incidentally by Aristotle – is that there exist similarities, isomorphisms, between the parts of organisms of very different species. These similarities, like those existing between the bones of the forelimbs of vertebrates, today known as “homologies,” are indeed powerful evidence of common ancestry, with one initial form having been molded to various ends (Figure 1.2). But the facts were always secondary to the ideology, that of progress.





© Cambridge University Press
Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Ch. 1 Charles Darwin and his revolution 5
Ch. 2 The fact of evolution 25
Ch. 3 The origin of life 52
Ch. 4 The path of evolution 72
Ch. 5 The cause of evolution 103
Ch. 6 Limitations and restrictions 134
Ch. 7 Humans 166
Ch. 8 Fact or fiction? 194
Ch. 9 Dishonest science? 214
Ch. 10 Philosophy 236
Ch. 11 Literature 258
Ch. 12 Religion 275
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Average Rating 5
( 1 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(1)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously
Sort by: Showing 1 Customer Reviews
  • Posted February 4, 2009

    For laity and modern scholars alike

    There is much to be learned from this book. It is extremely well annotated. Michael Ruse quotes others liberally, giving credit where credit is due. To others he extends the benefit of doubt. Ruse is careful not to offend those who discontend. We applaud him for that. In less than 300 pages of paperback, Ruse presents both sides of the Darwin question. He does a remarkable and even-handed job in recreating Darwin's thinking. He also illustrates well what biological science is really about.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
Sort by: Showing 1 Customer Reviews

If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
Why is this product inappropriate?
Comments (optional)