Hate Speech, Sex Speech, Free Speech

Overview

A powerful indictment of contemporary attacks on free speech, this book argues for a vigorous First Amendment jurisprudence protecting even offensive types of speech. In recent years, political activists, academics, and legal specialists have attacked traditional notions of free speech protection as they concern hate speech, obscenity, and pornography. They have called for changes in Supreme Court doctrine in defining the First Amendment and have argued that the traditional view of free speech actually creates ...

See more details below
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (5) from $2.74   
  • New (1) from $90.82   
  • Used (4) from $2.74   
Sending request ...

Overview

A powerful indictment of contemporary attacks on free speech, this book argues for a vigorous First Amendment jurisprudence protecting even offensive types of speech. In recent years, political activists, academics, and legal specialists have attacked traditional notions of free speech protection as they concern hate speech, obscenity, and pornography. They have called for changes in Supreme Court doctrine in defining the First Amendment and have argued that the traditional view of free speech actually creates and perpetuates a society in which the weak—women, minorities, the poor—have no voice. While recognizing their fears, Nicholas Wolfson argues that it is impossible to separate bad speech from good speech without fatally compromising the uniquely American concept of free speech, and that efforts to modify our concept of free speech for a greater egalitarian good can only result in undue state influence over private speech. In a keenly argued analysis, he finds that, in the end, the preservation of free and vigorous speech requires a strong First Amendment protection for even the most hateful of speech.

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Choice
"This volume should be required reading for all those who have been taken in by the faulty arguments of Richard Delgado, Dinesh D'Souza, Catharine MacKinnon, and their followers.... highly recommended for all academic, public, and professional collections."
Eugene Volokh
"A thoughtful, closely reasoned, and accessible defense of free speech and free inquiry-an extremely valuable contribution to the debate."
The Hartford Courant
"One of the most cogent analyses of the minefield of sensitive speech was published...in [this] book."
Booknews
Argues for a vigorous jurisprudence protecting even offensive types of speech, and claims that it is impossible to separate bad speech from good speech without fatally compromising the uniquely American concept of free speech. The author points out that truth is ascertained by a process of debate and conversation, and that even well intended editing of expressions of sex or hate may lead to censorship of a great swath of learned and sacred works. Annotation c. by Book News, Inc., Portland, Or.
Jerome O'Callaghan
Against the backdrop of ongoing controversies over hate speech and pornography, Nicholas Wolfson, the George and Helen England Professor of Law at the University of Connecticut, has developed a stimulating and passionate argument for increasing the scope of the free speech guarantee. Professor Wolfson's volume, developed in part from his earlier law review work, takes the form of a defense against the threat posed to traditional free speech doctrines by critics such as Mari Matsuda, Catharine Mackinnon and Charles Lawrence. Professor Wolfson proposes to fight the good fight on behalf of a more libertarian approach to speech; in so doing he aims to provide a persuasive answer to the central question: "Why should we permit hateful or sexually offensive speech?" The first chapter is a general introduction to the free speech battlefield. Traditional liberal approaches to free speech are under attack by feminists and minorities who seek to expand the power of the state to regulate offensive speech. Speech, however, has a central role in the development of our world and our understanding of ourselves; when it is threatened we face a "leveling of speech [which] might reduce and diminish the human spirit." (p. 5) Wolfson underlines the irony here: groups formerly denied access to power currently seek to change the very rules that aided their cause(s). The changes they propose are, in Wolfson's view, clearly detrimental to core free speech values. In the second chapter Professor Wolfson explains the relationship between truth, free speech and pragmatism. He argues that truth is simply the product of consensus, that consensus can never be final, and that a liberal approach to free speech protects the societal "conversation" that epitomizes our search for truth. His sources are a diverse group: Jacques Derrida, John Dewey, Charles Pierce and Richard Posner. As Posner puts it: "Truth is what free inquiry--unforced, undistorted, and uninterrupted--would eventually discover about the objects of inquiry. Since the process of inquiry never ends, this implies that truth always lies beyond our horizon: it is there but we aren't." (p. 18) Consequently those who assert the power to ban some speech from the Holmesian marketplace are implicitly asserting a knowledge of indisputable truth. This is an absolutism that Wolfson cannot abide: "Absolutism in every form is fundamentally contrary to First Amendment doctrine." (p. 26) Wolfson identifies three primary reasons to support "strong free speech." Speech is critical to: a) the search for an elusive truth, b) the advance of democracy, and c) the development of human autonomy. In all three instances, society can only lose if some groups act as censors in the marketplace of ideas. Our lack of certainty about what is good for democracy, good for truth, or good for our own development, should instruct us to leave our minds open to any speech that could be persuasive. That is the core of the pragmatic approach. As for the Supreme Court, it has disappointed Wolfson in its half-hearted embrace of pragmatism. Acting vigorously to protect political speech (a good thing), it has not offered the same level of protection to commercial speech (a bad thing). The Court has also made the mistake of denying obscenity free speech protection--although the concession to speech of serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value goes part way to pleasing the pragmatists. Wolfson also criticizes current defamation law: allowing individual courts to rule on truth/falsity is at odds with underlying pragmatic principles. Throughout this argument Wolfson relies heavily on the slippery slope analogy. If we allow feminists and minorities to punish "unpopular speech" today, there is no telling where that process will end. Thus while racist/sexist may cause problems, the cure of censorship is worse than the disease. Chapter three is devoted to hate speech alone. In fear of a free market of ideas "limited to bloodless cerebral cogitation" (p. 48), Wolfson is willing to defend the protection of hate speech. The First Amendment's purpose is to safeguard speech that the government deems harmful. Various means of attacking hate speech are analyzed and found wanting. Defamation law "chills free speech" and rests on a "frequently impossible distinction" between facts and opinions (p. 49). The suggestion that only epithets be subject to penalty is also a problem: it protects highbrow forms of insults that are no better than the "kike" or "nigger" used on the street. (Wolfson cites Shakespeare and the Bible among the highbrow hate speech genre). Some argue that hate speech has no content and for that reason should lose legal protection. Wolfson counters that much mass entertainment lacks content as well. Some argue that hate speech is punishable because it causes emotional distress--Wolfson counters that much intellectual debate is distressing to the participants, but that is no reason to ban it. He might well have relied on the wit of George Bernard Shaw: "All great truths begin as blasphemies." The most striking argument presented in this section concerns the proposition that speech is punishable when it causes harm. Wolfson disagrees; using harm as a criterion opens the door to "government thought control" (p. 57). Harm is too subjective; we risk the return of the "disreputable fighting words doctrine" (p. 63). Pervasive as ever is the risk of the slippery slope. He does allow one exception: "speech that is too closely brigaded with (simple) violent behavior is not protected." (p. 59) This, as scholars of First Amendment law will recognize, is a restatement of the Supreme Court decision in BRANDENBURG V OHIO. In the fourth chapter Wolfson addresses the question of inequality. His objective is to reveal how the arguments of feminists and minorities are based on a loss of faith in the marketplace of ideas. They rely on victim status to argue for retaliatory regulation in the form of "equalizing" speech. Wolfson links such propositions to elitism, and to the "old argument of orthodox Marxists" (p 85.) He contemplates a world where "[s]peeches, books and articles emphasizing the role of women in the home may be censored." (p. 91) Further, to equalize speech requires a process of selecting favored minority groups (women--yes, skinheads--no?), followed by an allocation of speech resources. Wolfson offers no examples of this phenomenon, but maybe government subsidy of public service advertisements would fit the bill. In any case, allocation will be a disaster; as Michael Novak notes, allocative systems simply "give superior benefits to those groups with superior organizational powers" (p. 89). The disenfranchised, the people at the heart of the inequality argument, will gain nothing. In the fifth chapter Wolfson turns to obscenity, pornography and eroticism--terms which, he says, refer to a dispute, not to anything concrete or harmful. He presents a brief but instructive history of pornography, emphasizing its political past (anti-aristocracy, pro-equality). He outlines the importance of homosexuality in western societies; he argues that matters of sexuality are more important than the banalities of political discourse given elevated status by the Supreme Court. On the question of feminist attacks on pornography, he relies on the opinion of Judge Easterbrook in AMERICAN BOOKSELLERS v HUDNUT. Easterbrook's analysis comes close to a pragmatic approach: it is best to allow insidious speech when the only alternative is to open the door to endless censorship (a.k.a. the slippery slope). While Professor Wolfson argues his case passionately, critical flaws are apparent throughout the text. From the beginning his analysis veers toward diatribe. Something is off-key when the first two examples of hate speech used by the author are: Huckleberry Finn and the Bible (both on page 1). We are a long way from burning-crosses on the lawn of a black family in the middle of the night (see R.A.V. v CITY OF ST. PAUL). On occasion he allows his suspicion of the enemy to veer toward paranoia: he links the analysis of Catharine Mackinnon to the Spanish Inquisition, he anticipates not just the marginalization of Plato, Aristotle and Locke, but "censorship [designed] to eliminate [their] influence." (p.76). His critics want a "powerful state organ to command speech equality" (p. 99). He demonizes the enemy by linking critics of current First Amendment doctrine to support of "affirmative action quotas, [and] the right to abortion on demand" (p. 39). At least five problems emerge in a close reading of the structure of his argument. First, if protecting the truth and avoiding harm fail to work as legitimate criteria for punishing speech, then surely we have fallen into First Amendment absolutism. He continually asserts that the First Amendment must protect offensive, harmful, false, injurious, distressing, worthless speech. With one brief exception, he sees no limit to that principle. He underestimates the slippery slope argument; it destroys all in its path. Any punishment of any form of speech opens the door for more censorship. Protection of all speech, no matter its content or consequences, is the only solution. But then on what ground can laws against perjury be maintained? And what about laws against child pornography? Second, the exception made for speech brigaded to immediate physical harm contradicts his own assertions: The "First Amendment is designed to protect speech that harms." (p. 58) If "harm ... is the measure by which we regulate speech there will be nothing left of the First Amendment." (p. 57) "The purpose of free speech protection is to safeguard speech that the government views as harmful." (p.49) Why is physical harm such a priority? (Why risk the danger of the omnivorous censor on the basis of a broken limb?). Is speech, which is destructive in a non-physical way (e.g. perjury) inevitably a low priority? Why does his Brandenburg position not create a slippery slope of its own? Third, Professor Wolfson identifies the usual categories of unprotected speech (fighting words, obscenity, defamation, and the "clear and present danger" zone) and finds fault with each. He ignores one other unprotected category of speech: child pornography (see NEW YORK V FERBER). Are there any good reasons to ban that aspect of free trade in the market of ideas? This is a particularly tricky subject, as his defense of sexual speech includes a description of the ancient Greeks approval of "man-boy" relationships. Wolfson is circumspect on this, acknowledging only that "the man-boy erotic relationship is especially problematical in modern Western society." (p. 116) His silence on the legitimacy of punishing producers of child pornography is deeply frustrating. Is another slippery slope emerging from the shadows? Fourth, the chapter on inequality raises many unanswered questions. It is the shortest of the four substantive chapters, partly because so little space is devoted to the significance of the Fourteenth Amendment. If he had addressed what the equal protection clause means, and more importantly, how it affects the First Amendment, he could have enhanced his argument substantially. Instead the Fourteenth Amendment first appears halfway through the chapter, it then plays only a cameo role. The inequality chapter does produce some good arguments, but, as he attacks a radical position, he identifies only one person who has made the radical claim (Mari Matsuda in a 1987 law review article). The whole exercise takes on a mountain-out-of-a-molehill quality. Fifth and perhaps most important, Professor Wolfson fails to address the advantages of a Supreme Court that is not constant in its free speech doctrine. Instead he naively assumes that once the Court allows some limit to free speech (say, defamation) then it will fall sway to whatever the censorious mob demands. However the historical record is more complex than that. Yes, the Court has fallen into wartime paranoia (he cites, correctly, the Communist speech cases of the 1950s). On the other hand the Court stood firm on flag burning, despite an overwhelming majority in the polity, and in the elected branches, against their decision. The Court also stood firm against a salute-the-flag mob in 1943, in war time no less. The fact that the Court is a creature of politics, and not an oracle of pragmatist truth, gives it an advantage in a system of checks and balances. Doctrinal inconsistency may be problematic to the First Amendment scholar, but it serves the Court well, and in the long run has served the First Amendment well. Theory and evidence suggest that the Supreme Court is usually able to distance itself from the trends and demands that plague the elected branches. Yes, First Amendment law has some slippery slopes, but the Justices have held the terrain quite well. Professor Wolfson's argument is certainly provocative and often instructive. Unfortunately it fails to provide a reliable principle for the development of free speech law. The dilemmas posed by hate speech regulation remain in place. Cases AMERICAN BOOKSELLERS v HUDNUT 771 F2d 323 (1985) BRANDENBURG v OHIO 395 U.S. 444 (1969) NEW YORK v FERBER 458 U.S. 747 (1982) R.A.V. v CITY OF ST. PAUL 505 U.S. 377 (1992)
From the Publisher

"This volume should be required reading for all those who have been taken in by the faulty arguments of Richard Delgado, Dinesh D'Souza, Catharine MacKinnon, and their followers…. highly recommended for all academic, public, and professional collections."

-

Choice

"One of the most cogent analyses of the minefield of sensitive speech was published…in the book Hate Speech, Sex Speech, Free Speech by Nicholas Wolfson."

-

The Hartford Courant

Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780275957704
  • Publisher: ABC-CLIO, Incorporated
  • Publication date: 9/5/2000
  • Pages: 182
  • Lexile: 1480L (what's this?)
  • Product dimensions: 5.50 (w) x 8.50 (h) x 0.56 (d)

Meet the Author

NICHOLAS WOLFSON is the George and Helen England Professor of Law at the University of Connecticut School of Law where he teaches courses in Free Speech, Securities Regulation and Corporate Law.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

1 Introduction 1
2 Pragmatism and Words That Hurt 11
3 Hate Speech 47
4 Inequality 83
5 Eroticism, Obscenity, Pornography, and Free Speech 103
6 Conclusion 143
Bibliography 151
Index 161
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)