Ignoring Nature No More: The Case for Compassionate Conservation

Overview


For far too long humans have been ignoring nature. As the most dominant, overproducing, overconsuming, big-brained, big-footed, arrogant, and invasive species ever known, we are wrecking the planet at an unprecedented rate. And while science is important to our understanding of the impact we have on our environment, it alone does not hold the answers to the current crisis, nor does it get people to act. In Ignoring Nature No More, Marc Bekoff and a host of renowned contributors argue that we need a new mind-set ...
See more details below
Paperback (New Edition)
$34.62
BN.com price
(Save 13%)$40.00 List Price
Other sellers (Paperback)
  • All (12) from $25.00   
  • New (9) from $31.32   
  • Used (3) from $25.00   
Ignoring Nature No More: The Case for Compassionate Conservation

Available on NOOK devices and apps  
  • NOOK Devices
  • Samsung Galaxy Tab 4 NOOK 7.0
  • Samsung Galaxy Tab 4 NOOK 10.1
  • NOOK HD Tablet
  • NOOK HD+ Tablet
  • NOOK eReaders
  • NOOK Color
  • NOOK Tablet
  • Tablet/Phone
  • NOOK for Windows 8 Tablet
  • NOOK for iOS
  • NOOK for Android
  • NOOK Kids for iPad
  • PC/Mac
  • NOOK for Windows 8
  • NOOK for PC
  • NOOK for Mac

Want a NOOK? Explore Now

NOOK Book (eBook)
$17.99
BN.com price
(Save 43%)$32.00 List Price

Overview


For far too long humans have been ignoring nature. As the most dominant, overproducing, overconsuming, big-brained, big-footed, arrogant, and invasive species ever known, we are wrecking the planet at an unprecedented rate. And while science is important to our understanding of the impact we have on our environment, it alone does not hold the answers to the current crisis, nor does it get people to act. In Ignoring Nature No More, Marc Bekoff and a host of renowned contributors argue that we need a new mind-set about nature, one that centers on empathy, compassion, and being proactive.
           
This collection of diverse essays is the first book devoted to compassionate conservation, a growing global movement that translates discussions and concerns about the well-being of individuals, species, populations, and ecosystems into action. Written by leading scholars in a host of disciplines, including biology, psychology, sociology, social work, economics, political science, and philosophy, as well as by locals doing fieldwork in their own countries, the essays combine the most creative aspects of the current science of animal conservation with analyses of important psychological and sociocultural issues that encourage or vex stewardship. The contributors tackle topics including the costs and benefits of conservation, behavioral biology, media coverage of animal welfare, conservation psychology, and scales of conservation from the local to the global. Taken together, the essays make a strong case for why we must replace our habits of domination and exploitation with compassionate conservation if we are to make the world a better place for nonhuman and human animals alike.
Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Michael Charles Tobias

“For years a small coterie of environmentalists, animal rights activists, ethicists, conservation biologists, philosophers, park management officials, and legislators have been grappling with the relationships between individuals and species; populations and habitats; bio-invasives and native and endemic species. What is the right thing to do with regard to listing threatened and endangered species? When is ecological legislation overreaching or, conversely, inadequate? At what point should humanity step in to resurrect past ecosystems, or prepare for climate-change-related future biomes? These and many other topics meant to help heal divisions between conservation biology and advocates of animal rights and animal welfare are forthrightly grappled with in Marc Bekoff’s important new, bold, eclectic, and forward-looking anthology, which scans the planet for flash points where animal protection and conservation biology are in direct correlation, conflict, ethically ambiguous point-counterpoint, or simply off the radar of most local, regional, and international discussion. This thoughtful book is a must-read for every student of zoology, ecology, environmental ethics, and conservation biology.”
Michael Soul�

“It may not be easy to be compassionate in this speedy, greed-ridden world, but maybe a person can be a bit kinder. Marc Bekoff and his fellow contributors make the case that an attitude of intelligent caring is both possible and essential if the world is to be saved.”
Will Stolzenburg

“Marc Bekoff has gathered here a remarkable field of thinkers to address humanity’s deepening estrangement from nature. Through the annals of history and science and literature, one message emerges clear: Our modern penchant for ignoring nature is not some harmless hiccup in an otherwise glorious human saga; it is a deadly sickness inflicting a world of impoverishment and misery for us and our fellow creatures. But in the case for compassion—for opening our hearts to the joys and sufferings of the world beyond our noses—we find a cure for our gravest threats, and at last, a reason for hope.”
Dale Jamieson

“I have mentored hundreds of idealistic young students over the years who have wanted to ‘save nature.’ They are shocked to discover that often what ‘saving’ means in practice is a single-minded devotion to killing and uprooting the unwanted, misplaced, ‘alien,’ or ‘exotic.’ Ignoring Nature No More is the sort of mash-up that has the potential to lead us away from this paradigm, towards treasuring life in all of its crazy, contradictory complexity.”
Daily Camera
“A selection of provocative but mostly accessible essays by scientists trying to answer such difficult questions as: When it comes to saving species, should we favor ‘charismatic’ animals like wolves over, say, ants?”
Humane Advisor

“An amazing collection.”
Michael Soule
“It may not be easy to be compassionate in this speedy, greed-ridden world, but maybe a person can be a bit kinder. Marc Bekoff and his fellow contributors make the case that an attitude of intelligent caring is both possible and essential if the world is to be saved.”
Boulder Daily Camera

“A selection of provocative but mostly accessible essays by scientists trying to answer such difficult questions as: When it comes to saving species, should we favor ‘charismatic’ animals like wolves over, say, ants?”
Animal People - Alexandra Semyonova

“Rich in insight and detail.”
Choice - M. LaBar

“A good choice for supplementary reading in animal welfare courses. . . . Recommended.”
Biological Conservation - Ian Werkheiser

“[W]ith this collection of thoughtful articles, as well as its inclusion of contact information for the authors, the book itself takes concrete steps toward bringing largely disconnected groups together to work on the complex problems of conservation.”
From The Critics

“It may not be easy to be compassionate in this speedy, greed-ridden world, but maybe a person can be a bit kinder. Marc Bekoff and his fellow contributors make the case that an attitude of intelligent caring is both possible and essential if the world is to be saved.”
BioScience

Ignoring Nature No More builds momentum for fur­ther work to refine the question: As Bekoff phrased it, ‘How can differ­ences between people concerned with individual animal welfare and those considered with species be resolved?’”
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780226925356
  • Publisher: University of Chicago Press
  • Publication date: 6/1/2013
  • Edition description: New Edition
  • Pages: 456
  • Sales rank: 1,098,472
  • Product dimensions: 6.00 (w) x 9.00 (h) x 1.10 (d)

Meet the Author


Marc Bekoff is professor emeritus of ecology and evolutionary biology at the University of Colorado Boulder. His numerous books include The Emotional Lives of Animals, The Animal Manifesto, and Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals, the last also published by the University of Chicago Press.
Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

IGNORING NATURE NO MORE

The Case for COMPASSIONATE CONSERVATION


By Marc Bekoff

THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS

Copyright © 2013 The University of Chicago
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-226-92533-2


Excerpt

CHAPTER 1

The Infirm Ethical Foundations of Conservation

John A. Vucetich and Michael P. Nelson


Introduction

THAT CONSERVATION HAS an ethical foundation is widely appreciated. Less appreciated is the shambled condition of that ethical foundation. This condition is revealed by our inability to answer questions like, What is population viability and ecosystem health? and, Is conservation motivated only to meet the so-called needs of humans, or also by respect for nonhuman populations and ecosystems? Some argue that this ethical uncertainty does not impede the effectiveness of conservation. We provide examples that suggest otherwise. We also explain how the source of ethical uncertainty is our mistaken tendency to think that the morality of our behavior should be judged more on the consequences of our actions and less on the motivations that underlie our actions.

Conservation's aim is often thought or said to be to maintain and restore population viability and ecosystem health. Achieving conservation is difficult, but the framework for conservation's goals seems in place: Use the best available science and the precautionary principle as input for a decision-making process that will suggest which actions will most likely lead to the most desirable outcomes; use politico-legal force to turn desired actions into law or policy; and include some environmental education (e.g., media and formal curricula) to build social support. That education almost always reduces to describing how humans affect natural systems, as if that will shock or shame us into supporting conservation.

This framework rests, unfortunately, on an infirm foundation that casts doubt on whether we really understand the aim of conservation. The answers to three questions illuminate the inadequacies of the foundation of conservation:

1. What is population viability and ecosystem health?

2. How does conservation relate to and sometimes conflict with other legitimate values in life, such as social justice, human liberty, and concern for the welfare of individuals, nonhuman animals? How should we resolve such conflicts?

3. Do populations and ecosystems deserve direct moral consideration?


These are the most important unanswered questions in conservation. Not having answers that are well defended and widely agreed upon has practical, on-the-ground consequences for conservation. Moreover, none of these questions are purely science questions. They are all philosophical or ethical in nature. This is disturbing because the ethics and philosophy of conservation may well be the most undertreated aspects of conservation. The very nature of conservation is, therefore, up for grabs because its ethical foundation is up for grabs. All the while, few people seem concerned. The need is not for each individual to answer the question in his or her own way; what is needed is the development of ethical consensus, which arises from ethical discourse (Nelson and Vucetich 2011).

An interlocutor might express skepticism: developing ethical consensus where there is none is impossible—not even among conservation professionals. Much evidence, however, speaks to our ability to develop ethical consensus (witness the abolition of slavery, women's suffrage, civil rights). Moreover, if we cannot arrive at a reasonably broad consensus about the three big questions above, then conservation's relationship to society will remain like a nation's tax policy: everyone agrees that tax policy should balance equality and fairness, socialism and libertarianism—but no one agrees on what that means. Instead, we should want conservation's relationship to society to be more like human medicine, which proceeds efficiently because we all agree on the aim (human health) and we all agree, more or less, on what human health means.

Answering "What is the aim of conservation?" is challenging because the question is broad and abstract, while at the same time the particulars of real conservation issues are so varied. It is difficult to identify principles that are general enough to entail most real issues, but not so broad and general as to be vacuous. To say that conservation is about maintaining and restoring population viability and ecosystem health is a bit too vacuous. By answering the three big questions, much that is vacuous will become firm. What follows is an exploration of how to approach the three big questions of conservation and the consequences of failing to take them seriously.


The Three Big Questions of Conservation

1. What is population viability and ecosystem health? Conventionally, population viability is assessed by estimating the probability that a population will go extinct over some time frame (Akçakaya, Burgman, and Ginzburg 1999). In principle, it is straightforward to estimate a population's extinction risk and to rank order extinction risk among a set of populations. In practice, both tasks tend to be especially difficult, in large part due to the limited availability of empirical data for most real populations.

Perhaps even more difficult is the task of determining the amount of extinction risk (the probability and time frame) beyond which a population would be considered endangered or not viable. For example, is a 5 percent chance of going extinct in 100 years an acceptably low chance of extinction? Or is a 10 percent chance of going extinct over 200 years more appropriate? No matter how extinction risk might be quantified, why is there so precious little discussion about such a profoundly basic question as, What is an unacceptable risk of extinction?

It seems straightforward to judge ecosystem health in the terms we use to describe ecosystems, that is, by: (i) their species richness and diversity; (ii) the nature of their ecosystem processes (e.g., nitrogen cycling) and ecological processes (e.g., predation or herbivory); (iii) temporal dynamics in these processes; and (iv) the spatial variation of ecosystems across landscapes (e.g., relative frequency of different kinds of ecosystems across landscapes).

One extreme, well-rehearsed perspective considers an ecosystem healthy to the extent that humans have not impacted it. From this perspective humans are a pathogen. Another extreme, well-rehearsed perspective considers an ecosystem healthy to the extent that it can continue providing resources and services that humans need. From this perspective humans are a parasite.

Our attempts to navigate this dichotomous notion of ecosystem health have been inept. For example, as we are increasingly faced with decisions about how to handle conservation-reliant systems (Scott et al. 2010), we find ourselves unable to avoid odd questions like, Is a human-altered ecosystem healthier when humans stop intervening, or when human intervention is used to return it to its prealtered state?

Another circumstance rises from our stumbling through the dichotomous view of ecosystem health. This circumstance, as odd as it is general, is represented by the question: On what portion of the landscape should we protect ecosystem health, and on what portion of the landscape should it be sacrificed for our use? The more familiar forms of this question are: How much wilderness and bioreserve area do we need? and, Should human impact be concentrated (e.g., intensive forestry on a small area) or diluted (e.g., less intensive forestry over a larger area)?

This attitude raises serious ethical questions, such as, On what ethical grounds can we justify respecting some ecosystems, but sacrifice others? This is Sophie's Choice manifest in our relationship with nature. The question also represents an ethical tragedy, a situation of our own making that seems to leave us with no acceptable choice. Moreover, this handling of the dichotomy never answers the question, What is a healthy ecosystem?

Despite the well-rehearsed problems with each perspective, each is rooted in a fundamental truth: humans can ruin ecosystems and humans need what ecosystems provide. But these perspectives also require believing that humans are separate from nature and require denying nature's intrinsic value. Both beliefs are unwise. Is it possible to develop a unified notion of ecosystem health that simultaneously recognizes: (i) humans can ruin ecosystems; (ii) humans need what ecosystems provide; (iii) humans are not separate from nature; and (iv) the value of healthy ecosystems for the sake of the ecosystem's interest, not just our own interest? What portion of conservation professionals concern themselves with this problem?


2. How does conservation relate to and sometimes conflict with other legitimate values in life, such as social justice, human liberty, and concern for the welfare of individuals, nonhuman animals? How should we resolve such conflicts? One approach to this question is to consider a useful definition of sustainability, which is "meeting human needs in a socially just manner without depriving ecosystems of their health [or populations of their viability]" (Nelson and Vucetich 2009c; Vucetich and Nelson 2010). Received definitions of sustainability suggest our unwillingness to, for example, sacrifice social justice in exchange for conservation and raise more particular questions like: Is it socially unjust to deprive a human community of their mode of living, if their mode of living deprives a nonhuman population of its viability or an ecosystem of its health? This question can be answered, but doing so requires: (i) a better understanding of what ecosystem health is; and (ii) an interest and ability to understand the nature of social justice, an interest and ability that seems well beyond the majority of conservation professionals and outside of the realm of what we normally think of as conservation science.

These questions would be ridiculous for anyone thinking that a particular conservation action was absolutely necessary for the survival or basic welfare of humanity. In that case, one might willingly pay almost any price for the conservation. The circumstance is, however, far more complex. Survival of the human species does not, for example, depend on Kansas having intact grassland ecosystems or the Pacific Ocean having blue whales. We already have a pretty good idea about how humans can survive without these populations or ecosystems.

Still, we cannot ignore the "13th rivet" metaphor, which explains how the loss of any particular species or ecosystem may not be important for the welfare of humanity, but the collective loss of many populations and ecosystems is. This raises the problem of how we go about deciding how we ought to treat any particular population or ecosystem. For every proposed conservation action, we must know how/whether the benefits of that particular action are worth the ethical costs that action might incur on social justice, or animal welfare, or whatever the costs may be.

The point is, conservation is not the only legitimate value in society. Particular conservation actions sometimes conflict with other values, and no particular conservation action always and automatically trumps every other value. Consequently, knowing conservation's role in society requires knowing how and why populations and ecosystems are valuable. In particular, we need to know how they are valuable beyond their utility to humans.


3. Do populations and ecosystems deserve direct moral consideration? This question is critical not only for conservation, and the academic field of environmental ethicists has generated a great deal of insight about how the question might be answered, though it is largely unknown to many conservation professionals.

An important line of reasoning has been that direct moral consideration should be extended to anything possessing a morally relevant trait. Many consider sentience and the capacity for reason to be morally relevant traits, and some consider them to be the only morally relevant traits. If so, ecological collectives would not deserve direct moral consideration because they are not sentient or capable of reason. Another school of thought known as biocentrism argues that being alive is the morally relevant trait. While some of these scholars argue that ecological collectives are morally relevant because they are living things, others argue they do not deserve moral consideration because they are not living individuals. Each of these approaches represents a kind of thinking known as extensionism.

By contrast, some professional ethicists have argued that ecological collectives deserve direct moral consideration because they are the will of some deity. Ironically, some theological consideration suggests that only humans deserve direct moral consideration.

Another more secular approach has been to argue that ecological collectives deserve direct moral consideration because they and we are members of a shared biotic community, and all community members deserve moral consideration. This was Aldo Leopold's contribution to environmental ethics. Deep Ecologists approach this question by first recognizing that humans deserve direct moral consideration, and then by recognizing that humans and ecological collectives are indistinguishable, and for these reasons ecological collectives deserve direct moral consideration.

In the process of developing these insights, some environmental ethicists have discovered a more basic challenge, which is, knowing what exactly is meant by the term direct moral consideration. First, as a matter of vocabulary, environmental ethicists generally say that a thing deserves direct moral consideration if it has intrinsic value, in contrast to having only instrumental (or use) value. The trouble is, what exactly is meant by intrinsic value.

Intrinsic value could be something that exists within certain things; implying intrinsic value is an objective property that can be discovered. In this case ethicists say to be intrinsically valuable is to be valuable in and of itself. However, intrinsic value may only exist in the mind of the valuer. In this case, intrinsic value would be value in addition to use value. Alternatively, intrinsic value may be more relational, that is, something that emerges from a valuer's relationship with certain things. Uncertainly about the meaning of intrinsic value amplifies the difficulty of answering the question, Do populations and ecosystems deserve direct moral consideration?

Answering this question would solve a great challenge for conservation. However, answering this question in the affirmative creates even more difficult ethical questions for conservation. Specifically, how to weigh and adjudicate among the disparate interests of humans and nonhumans.
(Continues...)


Excerpted from IGNORING NATURE NO MORE by Marc Bekoff. Copyright © 2013 by The University of Chicago. Excerpted by permission of The University of Chicago Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents


Foreword
Benjamin B. Beck

Preface
Who Lives, Who Dies, and Why
It Shouldn’t Be All about Us

Acknowledgments

Part One    Ethics, Conservation, and Animal Protection
Trying to Make Difficult Decisions Easier

1   The Infirm Ethical Foundations of Conservation
John A. Vucetich and Michael P. Nelson

2   Venturing beyond the Tyranny of Small Differences
The Animal Protection Movement, Conservation, and Environmental Education
Paul Waldau

3   Ecocide and the Extinction of Animal Minds
Eileen Crist

4   Talking about Bushmeat
Dale Peterson

5   Conservation, Animal Rights, and Human Welfare
A Pragmatic View of the “Bushmeat Crisis”
Ben A. Minteer

Part 2    Conservation Behavior and “Enlightened Management”
Guidelines for Restoring, Recreating, and Redecorating Nature

6   Why We Really Don’t Care about the Evidence in Evidence-Based Decision Making in Conservation (and How to Change This)
Daniel T. Blumstein

7   Cautionary Wildlife Tales
Learning to Fail or Failing to Learn?
Joel Berger

8   Coyotes, Compassionate Conservation, and Coexistence
Why Ignoring Nature Means Ineffective “Predator Management”
Camilla H. Fox

9   Why Evolutionary Biology Is Important for Conservation
Toward Evolutionarily Sustainable Harvest Management
Marco Festa-Bianchet

10   Reintroductions to “Ratchet Up” Public Perceptions of Biodiversity
Reversing the Extinction of Experience through Animal Restorations
Philip J. Seddon and Yolanda van Heezik

11   Przewalski’s Horses and Red Wolves
Importance of Behavioral Research for Species Brought Back from the Brink of Extinction
Sarah R. B. King

12   Why Individuals Matter
Lessons in Animal Welfare and Conservation
Liv Baker

Part 3    Conservation Economics and Politics
It All Comes Down to Money

13   The Imperative of Steady State Economics for Wild Animal Welfare
Brian Czech

14   Conservation, Biodiversity, and Tourism in New Zealand
Engaging with the Conservation Economy
Eric J. Shelton

Part Four    Human Dimensions of Social Justice, Empathy, and Compassion for Animals and Other Nature

15   Anthropological Perspectives on Ignoring Nature
Barbara J. King

16   Nature and Animals in Human Social Interactions
Fostering Environmental Identity
Susan Clayton

17   Conservation Social Work
The Interconnectedness of Biodiversity Health and Human Resilience
Philip Tedeschi, Sarah M. Bexell, and Jolie NeSmith

18   The War on Nature—Turning the Tide?
Lessons from Other Movements and Conservation History
David Johns

19   Consuming Nature
The Cultural Politics of Animals and the Environment in the Mass Media
Carrie Packwood Freeman and Jason Leigh Jarvis

20   Children, Animals, and Social Neuroscience
Empathy, Conservation Education, and Activism
Olin E. “Gene” Myers Jr.

Part 5    Culture, Religion, and Spirituality
Using Empathy and Compassion to Develop a Unified Global Movement to Protect Animals and Their Homes

21   Compassionate Conservation
A Paradigm Shift for Wildlife Management in Australasia
Daniel Ramp, Dror Ben-Ami, Keely Boom, and David B. Croft

22   China’s Wildlife Crisis
Cultural Tradition or Politics of Development
Peter J. Li

23   A Triangular Playing Field
The Social, Economic, and Ethical Context of Conserving India’s Natural Heritage
Vivek Menon

24   Conservation and Its Challenges in Kenya
Josphat Ngonyo and Mariam Wanjala

25   Is Green Religion an Oxymoron?
Biocultural Evolution and Earthly Spirituality
Bron Taylor

26   Avatar
The Search for Biosynergy and Compassion
Anthony L. Rose and A. Gabriela Rose

Some Closing Words
Moving Ahead with Heart, Peace, and Compassion
Marc Bekoff

About the Contributors
Contributors’ Contact Information
Index

Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)