Justice as Fairness: A Restatement / Edition 1

Justice as Fairness: A Restatement / Edition 1

ISBN-10:
0674005112
ISBN-13:
9780674005112
Pub. Date:
05/16/2001
Publisher:
Harvard University Press
ISBN-10:
0674005112
ISBN-13:
9780674005112
Pub. Date:
05/16/2001
Publisher:
Harvard University Press
Justice as Fairness: A Restatement / Edition 1

Justice as Fairness: A Restatement / Edition 1

$34.0
Current price is , Original price is $34.0. You
$34.00 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Not Eligible for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores
$13.20 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM

    Temporarily Out of Stock Online

    Please check back later for updated availability.

    • Condition: Good
    Note: Access code and/or supplemental material are not guaranteed to be included with used textbook.

Overview

This book originated as lectures for a course on political philosophy that Rawls taught regularly at Harvard in the 1980s. In time the lectures became a restatement of his theory of justice as fairness, revised in light of his more recent papers and his treatise Political Liberalism (1993). As Rawls writes in the preface, the restatement presents "in one place an account of justice as fairness as I now see it, drawing on all [my previous] works." He offers a broad overview of his main lines of thought and also explores specific issues never before addressed in any of his writings.

Rawls is well aware that since the publication of A Theory of Justice in 1971, American society has moved farther away from the idea of justice as fairness. Yet his ideas retain their power and relevance to debates in a pluralistic society about the meaning and theoretical viability of liberalism. This book demonstrates that moral clarity can be achieved even when a collective commitment to justice is uncertain.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780674005112
Publisher: Harvard University Press
Publication date: 05/16/2001
Edition description: New Edition
Pages: 240
Sales rank: 1,075,679
Product dimensions: 6.12(w) x 9.25(h) x 0.50(d)

About the Author

John Rawls was James Bryant Conant University Professor at Harvard University. He was recipient of the 1999 National Humanities Medal.

Erin Kelly is Professor of Philosophy at Tufts University.

Read an Excerpt


Chapter One


PART I

Fundamental Ideas


§1. Four Roles of Political Philosophy


    1.1. We begin by distinguishing four roles that political philosophy may have as part of a society's public political culture. Consider first its practical role arising from divisive political conflict and the need to settle the problem of order.

    There are long periods in the history of any society during which certain basic questions lead to deep and sharp conflict and it seems difficult if not impossible to find any reasoned common ground for political agreement. To illustrate, one historical origin of liberalism is the Wars of Religion in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries following the Reformation; these divisions opened a long controversy about the right of resistance and liberty of conscience, which eventually led to the formulation and often reluctant acceptance of some form of the principle of toleration. The views in Locke's Letter on Toleration (1689) and Montesquieu's The Spirit of Laws (1748) have a long prehistory. Hobbes's Leviathan (1652)—surely the greatest work of political philosophy in English—is concerned with the problem of order during the turmoil of the English civil war; and so also is Locke's Second Treatise (also 1689). To illustrate in our own case how divisive conflict may lead to political philosophy, recall the extensive debates between Federalists and Anti-Federalists in 1787-88 over ratification of the Constitution, and how the question Of the extension of slavery in the years before the CivilWar called forth fundamental discussions of that institution and of the nature of the union between the states.

    We suppose, then, that one task of political philosophy—its practical role, let's say—is to focus on deeply disputed questions and to see whether, despite appearances, some underlying basis of philosophical and moral agreement can be uncovered. Or if such a basis of agreement cannot be found, perhaps the divergence of philosophical and moral opinion at the root of divisive political differences can at least be narrowed so that social cooperation on a footing of mutual respect among citizens can still be maintained.

    To fix ideas, consider the conflict between the claims of liberty and the claims of equality in the tradition of democratic thought. Debates over the last two centuries or so make plain that there is no public agreement on how basic institutions are to be arranged so as to be most appropriate to the freedom and equality of democratic citizenship. There is a divide between the tradition derived from Locke, which stresses what Constant called "the liberties of the moderns"—freedom of thought and liberty of conscience, certain basic rights of the person and of property, and the rule of law—and the tradition derived from Rousseau, which stresses what Constant called "the liberties of the ancients"—the equal political liberties and the values of public life. This overstylized contrast brings out the depth of the conflict.

    This conflict is rooted not only in differences of social and economic interests but also in differences between general political, economic, and social theories about how institutions work, as well as in different views about the probable consequences of public policies. Here we focus on another root of the conflict: the different philosophical and moral doctrines that deal with how the competing claims of liberty and equality are to he understood, how they are to be ordered and weighed against each other, and how any particular way of ordering them is to be justified.


    1.2. I note briefly three other roles of political philosophy which we consider further as we proceed. One is that political philosophy may contribute to how a people think of their political and social institutions as a whole, and their basic aims and purposes as a society with a history—a nation—as opposed to their aims and purposes as individuals, or as members of families and associations. Moreover, the members of any civilized society need a conception that enables them to understand themselves as members having a certain political status—in a democracy, that of equal citizenship—and how this status affects their relation to their social world.

    This need political philosophy may try to answer, and this role I call that of orientation. The idea is that it belongs to reason and reflection (both theoretical and practical) to orient us in the (conceptual) space, say, of all possible ends, individual and associational, political and social. Political philosophy, as a work of reason, does this by specifying principles to identify reasonable and rational ends of those various kinds, and by showing how those ends can cohere within a well-articulated conception of a just and reasonable society. Such a conception may offer a unified framework within which proposed answers to divisive questions can be made consistent and the insights gained from different kinds of cases can be brought to bear on one another and extended to other cases.


    1.3. A third role, stressed by Hegel in his Philosophy of Right (1821), is that of reconciliation: political philosophy may try to calm our frustration and rage against our society and its history by showing us the way in which its institutions, when properly understood from a philosophical point of view, are rational, and developed over time as they did to attain their present, rational form. This fits one of Hegel's well-known sayings: "When we look at the world rationally, the world looks rationally back." He seeks for us reconciliation—Versöhnung—that is, we are to accept and affirm our social world positively, not merely to be resigned to it.

    We shall be concerned with this role of political philosophy in several respects. Thus I believe that a democratic society is not and cannot be a community, where by a community I mean a body of persons united in affirming the same comprehensive, or partially comprehensive, doctrine. The fact of reasonable pluralism which characterizes a society with free institutions makes this impossible. This is the fact of profound and irreconcilable differences in citizens' reasonable comprehensive religious and philosophical conceptions of the world, and in their views of the moral and aesthetic values to be sought in human life. But this fact is not always easy to accept, and political philosophy may try to reconcile us to it by showing us the reason and indeed the political good and benefits of it.

    Again, political society is not, and cannot be, an association. We do not enter it voluntarily. Rather we simply find ourselves in a particular political society at a certain moment of historical time. We might think our presence in it, our being here, is not free. In what sense, then, can citizens of a democracy be free? Or as we shall ask eventually, what is the outer limit of our freedom (§26)?

    One can try to deal with this question by viewing political society in a certain way, namely, as a fair system of cooperation over time from one generation to the next, where those engaged in cooperation are viewed as free and equal citizens and normal cooperating members of society over a complete life. We then try to formulate principles of political justice such that if the basic structure of society—the main political and social institutions and the way they fit together as one scheme of cooperation—satisfies those principles, then we can say without pretense and fakery that citizens are indeed free and equal.


    1.4. The fourth role is a variation of the previous one. We view political philosophy as realistically utopian: that is, as probing the limits of practicable political possibility. Our hope for the future of our society rests on the belief that the social world allows at least a decent political order, so that a reasonably just, though not perfect, democratic regime is possible. So we ask: What would a just democratic society be like under reasonably favorable but still possible historical conditions, conditions allowed by the laws and tendencies of the social world? What ideals and principles would such a society try to realize given the circumstances of justice in a democratic culture as we know them? These circumstances include the fact of reasonable pluralism. This condition is permanent as it persists indefinitely under free democratic institutions.

    The fact of reasonable pluralism limits what is practicably possible under the conditions of our social world, as opposed to conditions in other historical ages when people are often said to have been united (though perhaps they never have been) in affirming one comprehensive conception. Eventually we want to ask whether the fact of reasonable pluralism is a historical fate we should lament. To show that it is not, or that it has its very considerable benefits, would be to reconcile us in part to our condition. Of course, there is a question about how the limits of the practicable are discerned and what the conditions of our social world in fact are; the problem here is that the limits of the possible are not given by the actual, for we can to a greater or lesser extent change political and social institutions, and much else. However, I shall not pursue this deep question here.


§2. Society as a Fair System of Cooperation


    2.1. As I said above, one practicable aim of justice as fairness is to provide an acceptable philosophical and moral basis for democratic institutions and thus to address the question of how the claims of liberty and equality are to be understood. To this end we look to the public political culture of a democratic society, and to the traditions of interpretation of its constitution and basic laws, for certain familiar ideas that can be worked up into a conception of political justice. It is assumed that citizens in a democratic society have at least an implicit understanding of these ideas as shown in everyday political discussion, in debates about the meaning and ground of constitutional rights and liberties, and the like.

    Some of these familiar ideas are more basic than others. Those we use to organize and to give structure to justice as fairness as a whole I count as fundamental ideas. The most fundamental idea in this conception of justice is the idea of society as a fair system of social cooperation over time from one generation to the next (Theory, §1: 4). We use this idea as the central organizing idea in trying to develop a political conception of justice for a democratic regime.

    This central idea is worked out in conjunction with two companion fundamental ideas. These are: the idea of citizens (those engaged in cooperation) as free and equal persons (§7); and the idea of a well-ordered society, that is, a society effectively regulated by a public conception of justice (§3).

    As indicated above, these fundamental intuitive ideas are viewed as being

Table of Contents

Editor's Foreword

Preface

Part I Fundamental Ideas

1. Four Roles of Political Philosophy

2. Society as a Fair System of Cooperation

3. The Idea of a Well-Ordered Society

4. The Idea of a Basic Structure

5. Limits to Our Inquiry

6. The Idea of the Original Position

7. The Idea of Free and Equal Persons

8. Relations between the Fundamental Ideas

9. The Idea of Public Justification

10. The Idea of Reflective Equilibrium

11. The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus

Part II Principles of Justice

12. Three Basic Points

13. Two Principles of Justice

14. The Problem of Distributive Justice

15. The Basic Structure as Subject: First Kind of Reason

16. The Basic Structure as Subject: Second Kind of Reason

17. Who Are the Least Advantaged?

18. The Difference Principle: Its Meaning

19. Objections via Counterexamples

20. Legitimate Expectations, Entitlement, and Desert

21. On Viewing Native Endowments as a Common Asset

22. Summary Comments on Distributive Justice and Desert

Part III The Argument from the Original Position

23. The Original Position: The Set-Up

24. The Circumstances of Justice

25. Formal Constrains and the Veil of Ignorance

26. The Idea of Public Reason

27. First Fundamental Comparison

28. The Structure of the Argument and the Maximum Rule

29. The Argument Stressing the Third Condition

30. The Priority of the Basic Liberties

31. An Objection about Aversion to Uncertainty

32. The Equal Basic Liberties Revisited

33. The Argument Stressing the Second Condition

34. Second Fundamental Comparison: Introduction

35. Grounds Falling under Publicity

36. Grounds Falling under Reciprocity

37. Grounds Falling under Stability

38. Grounds against the Principle of Restricted Utility

39. Comments on Equality

40. Concluding Remarks

Part IV Institutions of a Just Basic Structure

41. Property-Owning Democracy: Introductory Remarks

42. Some Basic Contrasts between Regimes

43. Ideas of the Good in Justice as Fairness

44. Constitutional versus Procedural Democracy

45. The Fair Value of the Equal Political Liberties

46. Denial of the Fair Value for Other Basic Liberties

47. Political and Comprehensive Liberalism: A Contrast

48. A Note on Head Taxes and the Priority of Liberty

49. Economic Institutions of a Property-Owning Democracy

50. The Family as a Basic Institution

51. The Flexibility of an Index of Primary Goods

52. Addressing Marx's Critique of Liberalism

53. Brief Comments on Leisure Time

Part V The Question of Stability

54. The Domain of the Political

55. The Question of Stability

56. Is Justice as Fairness Political in the Wrong Way?

57. How Is Political Liberalism Possible?

58. An Overlapping Consensus Not Utopian

59. A Reasonable Moral Psychology

60. The Good of Political Society

Index

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews