Moral Imagination: From Edmund Burke to Lional Trilling

Overview

Gertrude Himmelfarb, one of America's most distinguished intellectual historians, here explores the minds and lives of some of the most brilliant and provocative thinkers of modern times: Edmund Burke and John Stuart Mill, Benjamin Disraeli and Winston Churchill, Jane Austen and George Eliot, Charles Dickens and John Buchan, Walter Bagehot and the Knox brothers, Michael Oakeshott and Lionel Trilling. In their distinctive ways, Ms. Himmelfarb argues, they exemplify what Burke two centuries ago and Trilling most ...
See more details below
Available through our Marketplace sellers.
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (11) from $2.97   
  • New (5) from $51.86   
  • Used (6) from $2.97   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing 1 – 3 of 5
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$51.86
Seller since 2007

Feedback rating:

(823)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
2006-04-07 Hardcover New NEW. NO remainder markings. A brand new book perfect inside and out. In a nice dj as well.

Ships from: Midland, VA

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
  • Express, 48 States
  • Express (AK, HI)
$97.86
Seller since 2008

Feedback rating:

(194)

Condition: New
1566636248 New. Looks like an interesting title!

Ships from: Naperville, IL

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$145.00
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(181)

Condition: New
Brand new.

Ships from: acton, MA

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing 1 – 3 of 5
Close
Sort by
Sending request ...

Overview

Gertrude Himmelfarb, one of America's most distinguished intellectual historians, here explores the minds and lives of some of the most brilliant and provocative thinkers of modern times: Edmund Burke and John Stuart Mill, Benjamin Disraeli and Winston Churchill, Jane Austen and George Eliot, Charles Dickens and John Buchan, Walter Bagehot and the Knox brothers, Michael Oakeshott and Lionel Trilling. In their distinctive ways, Ms. Himmelfarb argues, they exemplify what Burke two centuries ago and Trilling most recently have called the “moral imagination.” Behind the drama of ideas that played itself out in the lives and writings of these individuals was the free play of the moral imagination. From her own long engagement with these subjects, Ms. Himmelfarb describes how each of these thinkers, coming from different traditions, responding to different concerns, writing in different genres, shared a moral passion that permeated their work. And it is the liveliness of their imaginations that makes their reflections—on politics and literature, religion and society, marriage and sex—sometimes unpredictable, often controversial, always exciting, and as illuminating and pertinent today as they were then. In this eminently readable book, Gertrude Himmelfarb captures the wit and wisdom—and foibles and frailties—of a dozen memorable writers and thinkers, statesmen among them. The Moral Imagination possesses the clarity and persuasion of Ms. Himmelfarb's best work.
Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Micahel J. Lewis
"With humane eye and abundant sympathy.... Himmelfarb shows her great flair for evoking a personality."
Commentary
Booklist
Enlightening, infectiously enthusiastic.
Joseph Bottum
"Gertrude Himmelfarb [is] our finest living historian of the nineteenth century."
First Things
John Wilson
Gertrude Himmelfarb displays her usual lucidity and good sense.... You'll not be bored in the company of this penetrating intelligence.
Christianity Today
Peter Heinegg
The writing is crisp and judicious...the overall picture is rich. Himmelfarb is still going strong.
American Magazine
Washington Times
Beautifully written . . . a manual for modern statesmanship.
—Arnold Beichman
Providence Journal
A joy to read . . . . These thoughtful, perceptive, and calm essays are oases of reflection and concern.
—Sam Coale
Publishers Weekly
The intellectuals celebrated in this pleasing collection of essays are not your father's conservatives but your great-great-grandfather's, provided he was a well-to-do English gentleman. Neocon historian Himmelfarb (One Nation, Two Cultures) specializes in Victorian Britain and profiles some of its leading writers and statesmen, along with philosophical forerunners and descendants, to probe the complexities of two centuries of conservative thought. In her subtly revisionist accounts, novelists Jane Austen, George Eliot and Charles Dickens become conservative-minded moralists; liberal philosopher John Stuart Mill emerges as a closet conservative, when not swayed by his father or wife; and "Tory Democrats" Benjamin Disraeli and Winston Churchill, both supporters of early social welfare programs, demonstrate the latent progressivism of conservative politics. Far removed from American-style free market fundamentalism, the strand of conservatism Himmelfarb traces is respectful of tradition, accepting of an organic class system softened and humanized by personal ties and manners, and suspicious of schemes to rationalize society. Despite her brief for this outlook's continued relevance, it seems less a coherent belief system than a reaction to the liberal and radical ideologies driving modernity. Still, Himmelfarb's stylish blend of literary criticism and intellectual history yields a stimulating reappraisal of a multifaceted and influential worldview. (Apr. 7) Copyright 2005 Reed Business Information.
Kirkus Reviews
In an impressive array of pieces-all previously published, most substantially revised-a historian examines the moral views of novelists, politicians and philosophers. Himmelfarb (The Roads to Modernity, 2004, etc.) deals with figures who for most will range from the familiar (George Eliot, Jane Austen, Charles Dickens, Winston Churchill) to the barely known-or unknown (Walter Bagehot, John Buchan). Himmelfarb writes with ease about these figures, as though she has somehow integrated them into her own capaciously conservative philosophy. Sometimes the questions she asks seem trivial: Why, for example, does Dorothea marry Ladislaw? she wonders in her discussion of Middlemarch. But that question sends her to the heart of Eliot's novel. The author praises Dickens for his moral imagination, for bringing "the poor into the forefront of the culture"-not as some sort of vague "class," but as individuals. There are flashes of humor, too: In a discussion of Austen, Himmelfarb confesses that she preferred Clueless to the 1996 film Emma, feeling the former was "more in keeping with the spirit of the original." The author examines, more or less rigorously, the novels written by political figures Disraeli and the aforementioned Buchan. For the latter's efforts, she has extracted some amusing passages, but she is perhaps a bit quick to excuse his racism and anti-Semitism. There is a graceful review of Penelope Fitzgerald's book about her relatives, the Knoxes (The Knox Brothers, 2000), concluding that it was the brothers' "character and beliefs" that made them significant. Not all of the writing is graceful, however. Some passages-especially in her essay on Trilling-are dense with -isms, thick withliterary allusions. Erudite and scholarly and brimming with quotations-qualities that will appeal more to those who reside in academe than in Spoon River.
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9781566636247
  • Publisher: Dee, Ivan R. Publisher
  • Publication date: 4/25/2006
  • Pages: 288
  • Product dimensions: 6.20 (w) x 8.78 (h) x 1.00 (d)

Meet the Author

Gertrude Himmelfarb's other books include The Roads to Modernity; One Nation, Two Cultures; The De-Moralization of Society; On Looking into the Abyss; Poverty and Compassion; Marriage and Morals Among the Victorians; Victorian Minds; Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution; and Lord Acton. In a distinguished career as an historian, she has received a great many honorary degrees and fellowships and, most recently, the 2004 presidential National Humanities Medal. She lives in Washington, D.C.
Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

The Moral Imagination

From Edmund Burke to Lionel Trilling
By Gertrude Himmelfarb

Ivan R. Dee

Copyright © 2006 Gertrude Himmelfarb
All right reserved.

ISBN: 1-56663-624-8


Chapter One

Edmund Burke Apologist for Judaism?

* One of the most moving experiences in my teaching career occurred after a seminar discussion of Edmund Burke's Reflections on the Revolution in France. A student came up to me to explain that she had missed the previous session because it was a Jewish holiday (a little-observed one, which I had quite forgotten), but she wanted to assure me that she had borrowed another student's copious notes. She also took the opportunity to tell me how much she valued the course and especially how affected she was by Burke's book, for it gave her a new understanding and appreciation of Judaism-of her Judaism, which was a rigorous form of orthodoxy (so rigorous that she had had to get a special dispensation to attend a secular university).

I confess that I had never thought of Burke as an apologist for Judaism in any form. Of Catholicism, yes, in France-and in England, according to Conor Cruise O'Brien, who sees Burke as a crypto-Catholic, a "slumbering Jacobite," whose attack on the French revolutionaries was really a polemic against the English who had illegitimately (so he thought) imposed the Protestant ascendancy on Ireland. But no one had ever accused Burke of being a crypto-Jew. Indeed, some students had been disturbed by the references in the Reflections to "Jew brokers" and "money-jobbers, usurers, and Jews," the classic expressions of anti-Semitism. They also noted that in his diatribe against the anti-Catholic agitator Lord George Gordon, Burke made a point of the fact that Gordon was a "public proselyte to Judaism," heir to "the old hoards of the synagogue, ... the long compound interest of the thirty pieces of silver." And they were only slightly mollified by Burke's suggestion that this convert "meditate on his Talmud, until he learns a conduct more becoming his birth and parts, and not so disgraceful to the ancient religion to which he has become a proselyte." But the student who found in Burke a rationale for her faith was less troubled by these lapses. What impressed her was his defense of tradition and religion-and of religion as tradition. This is what spoke to her, as an Orthodox Jew, so directly and powerfully.

Tradition is, indeed, one of the main motifs of the Reflections-the crucial distinction, as Burke saw it, between the French Revolution and the English "Glorious Revolution" a century earlier. Where the French sought to create a society de novo, based upon principles dictated by reason, the English, even in the midst of their revolution, had tried to retain as much of the past as possible. The English revolutionaries, he explained, wanted nothing more than "to preserve our ancient indisputable laws and liberties, and that ancient constitution of government which is our only security for law and liberty." To make of the revolution itself "an inheritance from our forefathers," they sought precedents in "our histories, in our records, in our acts of parliament and journals of parliament," going back to that "ancient charter," the Magna Charta, and beyond that to "the still more ancient standing law of the kingdom." This, Burke emphasized (the italics were his), was the "pedigree," the "patrimony," the "hereditary title," the "entailed inheritance" of England's liberties.

Burke conceded that the English lawyers citing those ancient documents might have got some of the details wrong. But this made their motive, their "powerful prepossession towards antiquity," all the more evident. Moreover, the past served not only to validate the revolution; it validated the future as well. "People will not look forward to posterity, who never look backward to their ancestors." And the past itself was not fixed and immutable; on the contrary, as the revolution itself proved, the past was the only security for reform. "The idea of inheritance furnishes a sure principle of conservation, and a sure principle of transmission, without at all excluding a principle of improvement. It leaves acquisition free; but it secures what it acquires."

The French revolutionaries, on the other hand, in destroying whatever of the past they could, also tried to destroy that most venerable of institutions, the church, thus denying the most basic of human impulses, religion. We know, Burke declared, that "man is by his constitution a religious animal; that atheism is against, not only our reason but our instincts; and that it cannot prevail long." If the French Revolution succeeded in subverting Christianity, he predicted, the void would be filled by "some uncouth, pernicious, and degrading superstition." (This prediction was borne out three years later, with the inauguration of the "Worship of Reason," complete with new Temples of Reason, a new calendar, new festivals, and new saints.)

As religion was rooted in human nature, Burke reasoned, so the church was in human society. For the church was one of the institutions that reflected "the rational and natural ties that connect the human understanding and affections to the divine," helping to sustain "that wonderful structure, Man." And the best kind of religious institution was a church establishment that was part of the state and yet, by virtue of its independent property, independent of the state. Such a religious establishment consecrated church and state alike. This was especially important in a parliamentary regime, for it imbued free citizens with a "wholesome awe," reminding them that they were not entirely free, that they were only "temporary possessors and life-renters" in the commonwealth and were accountable to "the one great master, author and founder of society." Such an establishment, moreover, did not preclude the toleration of other religions. On the contrary, unlike unbelievers who tolerate other religions out of neglect or contempt, an establishment like that of the English tolerates them out of respect. The English "reverently and affectionately protect all religions, because they love and venerate the great principle upon which they all agree, and the great object to which they are all directed."

My student could have found a vindication of her faith elsewhere. Certainly she could have found it, or something very like it, in Maimonides or other authorities. But Burke gave her a more universal, less parochial justification of her faith as well as a better understanding of it in relation to her own time and place. Where Burke challenged an Enlightenment that, in the name of reason, threatened Christianity, she saw Jewish orthodoxy not threatened, to be sure, but demeaned by the enlightened secular ideology of her own age. And where he defended the idea of an established yet tolerant church, she recognized such a de facto establishment in her own dominantly Christian yet tolerant society-and, indeed, in the de jure yet tolerant Jewish establishment in Israel.

More important was the role Burke attached to tradition, in religion as in society. Burke has been criticized for being overly deferential to tradition and history and insufficiently respectful of both reason and revelation. If this is so, it is less a problem for Judaism than for Christianity. No religion is as tradition-bound and history-centered as Judaism. And Orthodox Judaism is all the more so. Of the 613 commandments prescribed for devout Jews, some are universal moral principles binding on all civilized human beings. But others are unique to Judaism; they are what distinguish it from all other faiths and peoples. To nonobservant Jews, some of these commandments seem arbitrary and irrational, relics of primitive customs and superstitions. For the Orthodox they carry the weight of law and morality because they have the mandate of authority-that of revered although not divinely ordained rabbis-and the sanction of tradition, of generations of ancestors.

Burke has also been criticized for having too utilitarian a view of religion, valuing it as an instrument of social cohesion and moral edification rather than as a personal, emotional spiritual experience. For Judaism, however, there is no dichotomy between the utility and the spirituality of religion. The observance of law and participation in the community of worshippers are so much a part of the religious faith that they enhance rather than diminish the spiritual experience, giving that experience a depth and a dimension it might otherwise lack. The idea that there is something spiritually demeaning or impoverishing in such an ethical, communal, "utilitarian" (as is said invidiously) religion is itself a product of the French Enlightenment, which denied the need for any transcendent basis for morality or community because it deemed reason to be self-evident and self-sufficient.

For most readers of Burke's Reflections-and for most of my students-the most disturbing passages in the Reflections were his vindication of "prejudice" and "superstition." These words were as provocative then as now, and deliberately so, for Burke used them purposefully to dramatize his differences with the French Enlightenment. For this Enlightenment, prejudice and superstition tainted all those aspects of life-habit, custom, convention, tradition, and religion-that were offensive because they seemed to violate the principle of reason. For Burke it was precisely those qualities that were the saving graces, so to speak, of civilized society-and, ultimately, of reason itself. Prejudice and superstition, he insisted, were not arbitrary or irrational. On the contrary, they existed in a continuum with wisdom and virtue, having in them the "latent" wisdom and virtue that had accumulated over the ages.

It was in the spirit of enlightenment-although not that of the Enlightenment as the French understood it-that Burke framed his defense of prejudice. The church establishment itself was a form of prejudice: "the first of our prejudices, not a prejudice destitute of reason, but involving in it profound and extensive reason." And all the other manifestations of prejudice had the same complementary relation to reason.

We are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of reason; because we suspect that this stock in each man is small, and that the individuals would do better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital of nations, and of ages. Many of our men of speculation, instead of exploding general prejudices, employ their sagacity to discover the latent wisdom which prevails in them. If they find what they seek, and they seldom fail, they think it more wise to continue the prejudice, with the reason involved, than to cast away the coat of prejudice, and to leave nothing but the naked reason; because prejudice, with its reason, has a motive to give action to that reason, and an affection which will give it permanence. Prejudice is of ready application in the emergency; it previously engages the mind in a steady course of wisdom and virtue, and does not leave the man hesitating in the moment of decision, sceptical, puzzled, and unresolved. Prejudice renders a man's virtue his habit; and not a series of unconnected acts. Through just prejudice, his duty becomes a part of his nature.

So, too, superstition, for Burke, existed in a continuum with reason-and with religion as well. In excess, Burke granted, superstition was a great evil. But, like all moral subjects, it was a matter of degree, and in moderate forms it was a virtue. Superstition was "the religion of feeble minds," which had to be tolerated in a mixture with religion, in some shape or other, "else you will deprive weak minds of a resource found necessary to the strongest." Burke was not arguing, as some have claimed, that superstition was necessary pour les autres, for the lower classes, still less that religion was necessary pour les autres. It was not particular men but "man" generically who was by constitution a religious animal." And it was all men, the strongest as much as the weakest, who had need of religion. Indeed, the strong required it even more than the weak, because they were more exposed to temptation, pride, and ambition, therefore more needful of the "consolations" and "instructions" of religion.

Finally, even more repugnant to the modern temper was Burke's paean to Marie Antoinette. "History will record," he promised, that momentous day, the 6th of October 1789, when "a band of cruel ruffians and assassins" descended upon Versailles, rushed into the queen's chamber, killing the guard and forcing the queen, "almost naked," to flee to her husband, where they were seized and taken to Paris, leaving behind a palace "swimming in blood, polluted by massacre, and strewed with scatterd limbs and mutilated corpses." That gory scene was followed by Burke's rhapsodic memory of his sight of the queen, then a dauphiness, sixteen or seventeen years earlier, "glittering like the morning star, full of life, and splendor, and joy." Little did he then dream that he would live to see such disasters fall upon her in a nation of "gallant men," "men of honour." Surely ten thousand swords would have leaped from their scabbards to avenge her. "But the age of chivalry is gone," he lamented. "That of sophisters, economists, and calculators has succeeded; and the glory of Europe is extinguished for ever."

"The age of chivalry is gone." And with it those sentiments-honor, reverence, loyalty, gallantry-that not only protected kings and queens but "kept alive, even in servitude itself, the spirit of an exalted freedom." This was the meaning of ancient chivalry in modern times. "Without confounding ranks, [it] had produced a noble equality, and handed it down through all the gradations of social life. It ... mitigated kings into companions, ... raised private men to be fellows with kings, ... subdued the fierceness of pride and power, ... obliged sovereigns to submit to the soft collar of social esteem, compelled stern authority to submit to elegance, and gave a dominating vanquisher of laws to be subdued by manners." But all of this was being destroyed by the Enlightenment.

All the pleasing illusions, which made power gentle, and obedience liberal, which harmonized the different shades of life, and which, by a bland assimilation, incorporated into politics the sentiments which beautify and soften private society, are to be dissolved by this new conquering empire of light and reason. All the decent drapery of life is to be rudely torn off. All the super-added ideas, furnished from the wardrobe of a moral imagination, which the heart owns, and the understanding ratifies, as necessary to cover the defects of our naked shivering nature, and to raise it to dignity in our own estimation, are to be exploded as a ridiculous, absurd, and antiquated fashion.

It took a bold and original mind, like Burke's, to make so radical a critique of the Enlightenment of his day-and of much of modernity today. And it took a brave and mature mind, like my student's, to see in that critique an explanation and appreciation of her own religion, which draws upon all the resources of history and humanity to sustain and invigorate itself: ancient traditions, the origins of which may have been lost in time; institutions and establishments, sanctified by age and experience, which bind people together in the common existence of daily life; prejudices and superstitions that betoken the larger truths of virtue and wisdom; and, not least, the "moral imagination" that gives heart and soul, as well as mind, to a living faith.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from The Moral Imagination by Gertrude Himmelfarb Copyright © 2006 by Gertrude Himmelfarb.
Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Edmund Burke : apologist for Judaism? 3
George Eliot : the wisdom of Dorothea 12
Jane Austen : the education of Emma 25
Charles Dickens : "a low writer" 36
Benjamin Disraeli : the Tory imagination 69
John Stuart Mill : the other Mill 94
Walter Bagehot : "a divided nature" 121
John Buchan : an untimely appreciation 135
The Knoxes : a God-haunted family 156
Michael Oakeshott : the conservative disposition 177
Winston Churchill : "quite simply, a great man" 197
Lionel Trilling : the moral imagination 219
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)