New Birth of Freedom: Abraham Lincoln and the Coming of the Civil War / Edition 1

Hardcover (Print)
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $1.99
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 95%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (7) from $1.99   
  • New (1) from $52.08   
  • Used (6) from $1.99   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$52.08
Seller since 2008

Feedback rating:

(17874)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
Brand New, Perfect Condition, Please allow 4-14 business days for delivery. 100% Money Back Guarantee, Over 1,000,000 customers served.

Ships from: Westminster, MD

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Close
Sort by

Overview

A New Birth of Freedom is the culmination of over a half a century of study and reflection by one of America's foremost scholars of American politics, Harry V. Jaffa. This long-awaited sequel to Crisis of the House Divided, first published in 1959, continues Jaffa's piercing examination of the political thought of Abraham Lincoln and the themes of self-government, equality, and statesmanship. Whereas Crisis of the House Divided focused on the famous senate campaign debates between Lincoln and Stephen Douglas, this volume expands and deepens Jaffa's analysis of American political thought, and gives special attention to Lincoln's refutation of the arguments of John C. Calhoun—the intellectual champion of the Confederacy. According to Jaffa, the Civil War is the characteristic event in American history—not because it represents a statistical frequency, but rather because through the conflict of that war we are able to understand what is fundamentally at stake in the American experiment in self-government.
Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Chicago Tribune
Continues the biography of Abraham Lincoln begun in Crisis of the House Divided.
CHOICE
Jaffa's prose is elegant and learned but complex, and, like his arguments, intellectually demanding. This absorbing book requires much effort on the part of the reader, but that effort is well rewarded.
First Things
Jaffa's new book has the same solid core that his earlier book possessed.
Religion & Liberty
A mighty achievement that will likely (and justly) dominate the landscape of American political thought for some time to come.
Liberty Press
Jaffa presents an impressive analysis of Lincoln in the context of Jefferson, Madison, Calhoun, and even William Shakespeare. A New Birth of Freedom is an outstanding book.
Civil War News
A New Birth of Freedom is a master work by a true and learned master of history and philosophy. It is a must for every serious student of the founding of our nation, of Abraham Lincoln, and of the Civil War. A New Birth of Freedom should be required reading for all lawyers, judges, members of political bodies, and of the body politic, and especially those still in school.
Journal of American History
The principal virtue of Jaffa's book is the seriousness with which it treats its main topic.
The Washington Times
No mere review can do justice to this new book; suffice to say that it is a stunning work of scholarship and erudition that vindicates Lincoln against both his contemporary adversaries and those who in our own time would diminish him and the principles of the American Founding he sought to perpetuate.
American Historical Review - Michael Vorenberg
Jaffa has again delivered a powerful contribution to Lincoln scholarship. Historians will find many riches in Jaffa's latest learned volume.
Civil War Book Review - Jean Bethke Elshtain
Harry V. Jaffa takes his time. The wait is well worth it. In unpacking Lincoln's great speeches and debate orations, Jaffa shows what an astute, formidable, and brilliant interlocutor Lincoln was.
George Anastaplo
On exhibit in this book is a powerful intellect. . . . Among the prominent Americans who are brilliantly illuminated here as they have rarely been are Thomas Jefferson, John C. Calhoun, Jefferson Davis, and, of course, Abraham Lincoln.
Herman Belz
A New Birth of Freedom more than meets the critical expectations that Professor Jaffa has invited in the years since his acclaimed study, Crisis of the House Divided: An Interpretation of the Lincoln-Douglas Debates, reoriented scholarly investigation of Abraham Lincoln and the coming the Civil War. A work of profound historical erudition and disciplined philosophical criticism, Jaffa's new work offers an original analysis of the crisis of the Union in the perspective of the western political tradition and in the context of the constitutional principles of the American Revolution. More judiciously than any other twentieth-century scholar writing in the nationalist tradition, Jaffa meets the challenge posed by the political philosophy and constitutional constructions of John C. Calhoun and the southern secessionists. Recognizing the openness of the historical situation that existed in 1861, Jaffa provides the most searching and fair-minded analysis of Lincoln's reasons for resisting secession that I have ever read.
James M. McPherson
Four decades ago, Harry Jaffa offered powerful insights on the Lincoln-Douglas debates in his Crisis of the House Divided. In this long-awaited sequel, he picks up the threads of that earlier study in this stimulating new interpretation of the showdown conflict between slavery and freedom in the election of 1860 and the secession crisis that followed. Every student of Lincoln needs to read and ponder this book.
Steven B. Smith
With A New Birth of Freedom Harry V. Jaffa reestablishes himself as the greatest living scholar of Lincoln's political thought and Lincoln's greatest defender, period. Jaffa's analysis of the First Inaugural is without parallel as he demonstrates once and for all the incoherence of Calhoun's arguments for the southern secession. For every citizen interested in the preservation of the American union and the principles on which it rests, Jaffa's book is a must-read.
William E. Gienapp
Harry V. Jaffa's A New Birth of Freedom is a brilliant and incisive explication of the political ideas that were at the heart of the coming of the Civil War. Jaffa is at his very best in demolishing the currently fashionable argument that the ideal of equality was not part of the American constitutional system from its beginning. This is a work of deep learning and great relevance, both to Lincoln's time and our own. It is a worthy sequel to the author's classic study, A Crisis of the House Divided.
Allen C. Guelzo
Forty years ago, Harry Jaffa wrote the greatest book on Abraham Lincoln's politics for a generation; now, Jaffa has written the greatest book on Lincoln's politics for another generation. A New Birth of Freedom is a relentless, powerful analysis of how Abraham Lincoln claimed the high intellectual ground of right, of universality, and of prudence from the romantic and racist ideology of John Calhoun—and claims it still from the shadow of Calhoun's postmodern imitators.
Hadley Arkes
Harry Jaffa's Crisis of the House Divided could rank as the 'first book' of American political science, for it showed how the whole tradition of political philosophy was brought to bear, by a gifted political man, on the gravest crisis of the American regime. For the same reason, that book stands, even today, as the best book ever written on Lincoln: it gave an account of Lincoln at the highest level, by actually taking seriously the substance of Lincoln's political thought. In A New Birth of Freedom, Jaffa provides the sequel, long-awaited. It is a sublime work, advancing and deepening the first. Lincoln comes out even more clearly in this new book as a model of 'classic statesmanship,' set off against all of the moral premises that would come with modernity, as Right and Left, would back into nihilism and reject the moral tradition. In Jaffa's hand, the account of Lincoln reaches the poetic, as indeed it must, for as the author allows, 'the place of the necessity in great poetry imposed by the artist may be occupied by a providential order in history, revealed in the speeches of the tragic hero.'
Peter Parish
Forty years after his Crisis of the House Divided, widely recognized as a classic analysis of the ideas articulated in the Lincoln-Douglas debates, Harry Jaffa has brought the same combination of impressive learning, breadth of knowledge and bold argument to his study of Lincoln's ideas at the outbreak of war. He places Lincoln's thought in a rich and broad context that ranges from Plato and Aristotle, and Dante and Shakespeare to Jefferson and Calhoun. This is a distinctive and provocative contribution to the current debate about the ideology and the ideals of America's greatest president.
The Weekly Standard - Glenn Tinder
The appearance of Jaffa's A New Birth of Freedom: Abraham Lincoln and the Coming of the Civil War is an intellectual event of some significance. . . . The new volume will not prove a disappointment. It is a product of rigorous reasoning, reflects a profound knowledge of Lincoln and his era, and is cast in vigorous prose. And like the earlier volume, it expresses a deep moral seriousness.
The State - Charles Sermon
In this deeply thought-out and eloquently argued book, the sequel to his acclaimed Crisis of the House Divided, Harry Jaffa brilliantly distills the political thinking of Abraham Lincoln and its potent legacy.
The Claremont Review Of Books - Charles R. Kesler
Jaffa shows the inner unity of Lincoln's words and deeds with an intelligence and loving care never before equaled.
The Wall Street Journal - Bret Stephens
The essence of Jaffa's case—meticulously laid out over nearly 500 pages—is that the Constitution is not, as Lincoln put it, a 'free love arrangement' held together by passing fancy. It is an indissoluble compact in which all men consent to be governed by majority, provided their inalienable rights are preserved.
Chicago Tribune - James L. Swanson
A New Birth of Freedom was worth the wait. Jaffa has produced a tour de force: an unabashed but scholarly celebration of Lincoln, liberty, and equality; a book that achieves Jaffa's goal of understanding 'the true measure of Lincoln's greatness.'
National Review - John Patrick Diggins
No other scholar has scrutinized the main documents of early American political thought as thoroughly as Jaffa. Prof. Jaffa's valuable book is as comprehensive as an encyclopedia and as exegetical as a scholastic thesis. Whether one agrees with him entirely or not, his argument that the ideas of Jefferson and Lincoln represent an organic continuity is original and daring and deserves to be debated for years to come.
Book World - Benjamine P. Tyree
Harry Jaffa has crafted a captivating study of Abraham Lincoln's decision to save the Union by force in the secession crisis following his 1860 election to the presidency. The author broadly examines the intellectual, moral, and legal bases of the American founding to show how Lincoln's positions were logically derived.
History - James A. Rawley
Erudition, brilliance, probing analysis of texts, and the relation of ideas to others. His [Jaffa's] writing is insightful, imaginative, argumentative, and usually persuasive. This book makes an important contribution to the study of Lincoln's thought.
Reviews In American History - Daniel J. McInerney
Scholars should add A New Birth of Freedom to their must-read list.
Rhetoric & Public Affairs
Jaffa's analysis of Lincoln and his rhetoric offers great insight. . . . One hopes that . . . Jaffa may enjoy a lifespan of Mosaic proportions and continue for many years to enrich our understanding of Lincoln.
The Anniston Star
This book is a scholarly effort. It is not an easy read, yet the logic Professor Jaffa offers flows clearly, orderly, and in abundance.
Publishers Weekly - Publisher's Weekly
At last Jaffa, professor emeritus of political philosophy at Claremont McKenna College, delivers the long-promised and very worthy sequel to his classic, Crisis of the House Divided (1958), which brilliantly synthesized the content and meaning of the Lincoln-Douglas debates. In his new work for the serious student of the 16th president's Jeffersonian interpretation of Constitutional law, Jaffa sees Lincoln's utterances in the debates as summarizing his political thinking from the time of the repeal of the Missouri Compromise (1854) up until his message to Congress on July 4, 1861. Starting with the July 4th address, Lincoln began to wrangle politically and intellectually with the legacy of John C. Calhoun and--more specifically--with Calhoun's arguments for states' rights and secession. Calhoun had built a rhetoric separating states' rights from natural rights; he claimed that his new political science superseded the Declaration of Independence, the Federalist thinking and that of the Founding Fathers in general. In this book's penultimate chapter--a fascinating critique of Calhoun's paradigm--Jaffa accomplishes what he set out to do and vindicates, in his own words, "not only Lincoln's rejection of the Southern states' rights dogma but also the intrinsic validity of the natural rights of the Declaration of Independence, encompassing the proposition that all men are created equal." This title, which features a stark and striking photo of Lincoln on its jacket, should sell on Jaffa's reputation--Rowman & Littlefield is planning a substantial first printing of 10,000 copies, and the author will do promotion in California, where he lives, and in Washington, D.C. (Nov.) Copyright 2000 Cahners Business Information.
Library Journal
After 40 years of ruminating on Abraham Lincoln and the coming of the Civil War, Jaffa has produced the sequel to his acclaimed A Crisis of the House Divided (1959). The author returns to the spoken and written record to discover how and why the Union came apart and how and why Lincoln, more than anyone else, made the case for the moral obligation to put it back together. Jaffa casts his study in the mode of a medieval commentary, parsing the words of Thomas Jefferson, John C. Calhoun, Jefferson Davis, and Lincoln to explore such ideas as equality, slavery, democracy, union, and history. Calhoun and Lincoln do most of the verbal jousting here, with Lincoln getting the last word on the exceptionality and necessity of the American democratic experiment, expressed so fully in the Gettysburg Address, which stands, with the Declaration of Independence, as the touchstone for Jaffa's analysis. The author shows that Lincoln's intellectual and moral imperatives embraced all humankind and, in the end, made him not only the champion of Union but the enemy of slavery. This dense, demanding book on political philosophy will repay many readings and is a powerful rebuttal of those who insist that passion alone drives history and that great men did not mean what they said. Recommended for academic libraries.--Randall M. Miller, Saint Joseph's Univ., Philadelphia Copyright 2000 Cahners Business Information.
Booknews
In this second of a projected three volumes on the political thought of Lincoln and his legacy, Jaffa (political philosophy, emeritus, Claremont McKenna College and Claremont Graduate U.) examines Lincoln's understanding of the concepts of self-government, equality, and statesmanship, as well as his refutation of the political philosophy and constitutional interpretations of John C. Calhoun and the southern secessionists. Annotation c. Book News, Inc., Portland, OR (booknews.com)
John Patrick Diggins
Prof. Jaffa's valuable book is as comprehensive as an encyclopedia and as exegetical as a scholastic thesis.
National Review
Kirkus Reviews
A masterful synthesis and analysis of the contending political philosophies on the eve of the Civil War. Jaffa (Political Philosophy/Claremont Coll.) modestly characterizes this towering work (a sequel to his Crisis of the House Divided, 1953) as "a commentary on the Gettysburg Address"—an understatement comparable to Melville describing Moby-Dick as a whaling manual. An unabashed admirer of Lincoln (he compares him to Socrates and Shakespeare), the author identifies the president's three "permanent and unchanging goals": "preserving the right of free elections, preserving the Union, and placing slavery in the course of ultimate extinction." Before examining many of Lincoln's public utterances (most beautifully, his first inaugural address), however, Jaffa looks back at the election of 1800 (the "first time in the history of the world" that political power passed peacefully) and reveals his expository technique: several steps backward precede each step forward. Neither Lincoln's beliefs nor those of his opponents can be properly understood without attention to antecedents. His fierce commitment to human rights must be seen in the light of the Declaration of Independence, the Federalist Papers, the Constitution—and their antecedents (Aristotle, Locke, et al.). This makes for a slow—but enormously rewarding—read. With devastating exactness, the author places explosive charges in the philosophical edifices of historian Carl Becker (whose 1922 book on the Declaration of Independence he blames for misleading generations of subsequent scholars) and political rivals Stephen Douglas and John Calhoun—then watches the ensuing implosion. Lincoln believed (asJaffadoes) that "right and wrong have an objective existence, . . . knowable by human reason, . . . binding upon the majority no less than the minority." The genius of Lincoln ("the truest heir of [George] Washington") is that he first recognized that the political equality of all is fundamental to democracy, then exerted his considerable intellect and political skill to achieve it. A magisterial work that arrives after a lifetime of scholarship and reflection—and earns our gratitude as well as our respect. Kershaw, Ian HITLER: 1936-1945: Nemesis Norton (832 pp.) Nov. 2000
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780847699520
  • Publisher: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
  • Publication date: 9/28/2000
  • Edition number: 1
  • Pages: 576
  • Product dimensions: 5.66 (w) x 8.22 (h) x 1.44 (d)

Meet the Author

Harry V. Jaffa is the Henry Salvatori Professor of Political Philosophy Emeritus at Claremont McKenna College and Claremont Graduate University, a distinguished fellow of the Claremont Institute, and the author of ten books.
Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt




Chapter One


The Election of 1800
and the Election of 1860


Our popular government has often been called an experiment. Two points in it our people have already settled—the successful establishing and the successful administering of it. One still remains—its successful maintenance against a formidable internal attempt to overthrow it. It is now for them to demonstrate to the world that those who can fairly carry an election can also suppress a rebellion; that ballots are the rightful and peaceful successors of bullets; and that when ballots have fairly and constitutionally decided, there can be no successful appeal back to bullets; that there can be no successful appeal except to ballots themselves, at succeeding elections.

—Abraham Lincoln


    Thus Abraham Lincoln wrote, nearing the conclusion of his July 4, 1861, Message to Congress in Special Session. When Lincoln sent this message, Fort Sumter had been attacked (April 12) and had surrendered (April 14). Lincoln had thereupon issued his call for 75,000 troops, instituted the federal blockade of Southern rebel ports, and suspended the writ of habeas corpus. The Civil War had begun.

    In his July 4 Message, Lincoln carefully elaborated the reasons why the rebellion had to be suppressed by force of arms. The first and most comprehensive reason was that it presented


to the whole family of man, the question, whether a constitutional republic, or democracy—a Government of thepeople, by the same people—can, or cannot, maintain its territorial integrity, against its own domestic foes.... It forces us to ask: "Is there, in all republics, this inherent and fatal weakness?" " Must a Government, of necessity, be too strong for the liberties of its own people, or too weak to maintain its own existence?"


Second, it was necessary, he said, to vindicate the Union against the "ingenious sophism" that "any State of the Union may, consistently with the national Constitution, and therefore lawfully, and peacefully, withdraw from the Union, without the consent of the Union or of any other State." Lincoln held that the alleged constitutional right of secession, as distinct from the natural right of revolution, was a prescription for anarchy. Third, it was necessary, as Lincoln put it in the epigraph of this chapter, to vindicate the principle of free elections. It was necessary to use bullets to establish the right, not of bullets, but of ballots to decide who should rule.

    It will, I believe, prove to be true that in Lincoln's mind the idea of a popular government that unites liberty and order, the idea of the Union, and the idea of rule by free elections are one and the same. Their inner unity may be said to resemble the Trinity, the three persons of God in Christian doctrine. But it is important, as in the case of Christianity, to understand the reasons for the distinctions within that threefold unity.


* * *


    That the legitimate authority of government is founded upon the sovereignty of the people, expressed in free elections under conditions of universal suffrage, is a proposition that is today virtually undisputed in Western civilization. In the world that witnessed the American Revolution, however, it was, to say the least, an idea still struggling to be born. In the world that witnessed the American Civil War, it was an idea whose meaning was fundamentally disputed and whose acceptance was unresolved.

    If we are to understand our past as those who lived it understood it, we must free ourselves of any illusion that the kinds of elections we now consider to be the only foundation of legitimate government are the usual or customary foundation of human government. That there "can be no successful appeal" from the ballot box as a means of deciding who shall govern, "except to ballots themselves, at succeeding elections," was the principle by which Lincoln, at the outset of the Civil War, justified the use of force to preserve the Union. But the idea of deciding who should govern by means of a free election by a whole people was something that the world had never known before the American Revolution. Most of mankind has always lived under what we, the heirs of the Founding Fathers and of Lincoln, call tyrannies. These tyrannies have differed among themselves. Recently, for example, we have been instructed in the differences between authoritarian and totalitarian regimes. No doubt this difference matters greatly to those who live under such regimes, just as it mattered during the Roman Empire whether one lived under a Marcus Aurelius or a Nero or Caligula. But it is well to remember that no subjects of the Roman emperors, whether the good emperors or the bad, had anything to say as to who that emperor was. It was the officers of the Praetorian Guard—the "colonels" of the army that ruled the empire of the Caesars—who decided who Caesar would be.

    Nor did the phenomenon of appealing to ballots alone in deciding who should govern emerge immediately as a consequence of the American Revolution. Indeed, we know of no example before 1800 of a government in which the instruments of political power passed from one set of hands to those of their most uncompromisingly hostile political rivals and opponents because of a free vote. The electoral contest of 1800 climaxed a decade of party warfare. The election of 1796, the first following the retirement of Washington (whose election had been virtually uncontested), was bitterly fought, but the incumbent party retained office. The political conflict intensified in the next four years, and its rhetoric exceeded in acrimony any in subsequent American political history, including that of the elections preceding the Civil War. Yet when the votes of 1800 (and 1801) had been counted and the election decided according to the forms of the Constitution, the offices were peacefully vacated by the losers and peacefully occupied by those who had prevailed. Nor were any of the defeated incumbents executed, imprisoned, expropriated, or driven into exile, as were the losers in the English civil wars and in the political contests of the Rome of Cicero and Caesar. The defeated Federalists went about their lawful occupations unmolested and for the most part engaged in the same kind of political activity in which their opponents had previously engaged. Again, to the best of our knowledge, this was the first time in the history of the world that such a thing had happened.

    It is natural at this point to ask, Why did those who failed to carry the presidential election of 1860 not accept the outcome of that election, as did the defeated Federalists of 1800? This question is necessary and proper. It must be preceded, however, by the question of how the astounding precedent of 1800 itself was established. A break with all previous human history is even more in need of explanation than a break with a precedent of only threescore years. What was it that persuaded or enabled Americans in 1800 to discover in free elections the basis, not merely for choosing a government, but also for choosing a government from one of two bitterly contending parties? More particularly, what enabled them to accept the results of an election in which each of the rival parties charged the other with being subversive of that form of government for which the American Revolution had been fought? Was compliance with the results of the voting in 1800 an acceptance of the idea "that ballots are the rightful and peaceful successors of bullets"? Or was Lincoln in 1861 placing an interpretation upon an event as governed by reason and principle that was in truth merely the fortuitous outcome of prevailing circumstances?

    The decision for political change heralded by the Declaration of Independence was authorized by a representative legislative body. But can we look upon it in the light of a decision made in consequence of a free election? In a famous letter to Henry Lee in 1825, in which Jefferson went to greater lengths than anywhere else to explain the purposes of the Declaration, he wrote that "with respect to our rights, and the acts of the British government contravening those rights, there was but one opinion on this side of the water. All American whigs thought alike on these subjects." While American Whigs may have thought alike, what of the Tories? In fact, those called Tories in the American Revolution suffered a fate not unlike that customary for defeated partisans throughout the ages. There were many instances of mob violence against them and of the destruction and confiscation of their property. It has been estimated that there were proportionately more refugees from the American Revolution than from the French Revolution. Indeed, British Canada has its origins largely in the emigration thus begun. Few of the émigrés were able to recover, or be indemnified for, their lost property, even though diplomatic attempts were made after the war to provide redress.

    From Jefferson's perspective, it would appear that only those who were "American whigs" within his meaning could be considered part of the political universe with respect to which majority rule would be possible. This means that had a plebiscite on independence been possible in 1776, Whigs would (if they could) have excluded Tories from the vote! What constituted an "American whig" was accordingly defined by the statement of principles in the Declaration of Independence, most notably by the passage beginning, "We hold these truths to be self-evident." We may therefore say that from the perspective of the Revolution, a free election can be conducted only among "Whigs"! And the acceptance of the idea of human equality, as that idea was comprehended within "the laws of nature and of nature's God," would appear to be the necessary condition par excellence for defining who might participate in a free election, and hence who might be expected peacefully to abide by its results. Only those can willingly submit to the results of an election who see it as a means of deciding how "to secure these rights." But the rights to be secured, which include "life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness," are understood a priori to be the equal rights of everyone, those who vote with the minority no less than those in the majority. A community can conduct elections with the expectation that all parties will accept the results only if the elections are preceded by a mutual recognition of the equal rights of the participants. But the rights of the participants in an election are rights under positive law. That the positive law should be one of equal rights can itself be understood as a necessary inference from the antecedent equality that subsists under "the laws of nature and of nature's God."

    One cannot imagine the issue that divided the Americans and the British Crown and Parliament being decided by a vote. In effect, this would have meant deciding whether or not to accept the Declaratory Act of 1766, which asserted that


the King's majesty, by and with the advice and consent of the lords spiritual and temporal, and commons of Great Britain, in parliament assembled, had, hath, and of right ought to have, full power and authority to make laws and statutes of sufficient force and validity to bind the colonies and people of America, subjects of the crown of Great Britain, in all cases whatsoever.


The "American whigs" of 1776 regarded the Declaratory Act to be, in principle, an assertion of a right to exercise despotic power over them. They would have seen a vote to accept it as a vote to accept slavery. Can anyone be asked to vote to enslave himself? Is not the very idea of an election to decide such a question an absurdity? Is it not also evident that someone for whom death is preferable to slavery cannot regard as a fellow citizen someone for whom slavery is an acceptable option? To be a fellow citizen means not only to be able to accept the results of a free election but also to be willing to fight to preserve, protect, and defend the regime of free elections. A community of citizens is a community of those willing to fight for each other. Someone who will not fight for you, when you are willing to fight for him, cannot be your fellow citizen.


* * *


    A great deal has been written in support of the view that, in the American Revolution, the Americans were fighting primarily and essentially to defend their rights as Englishmen under the positive law of the British constitution. A leading exponent of this point of view is Russell Kirk, who writes:


Until 1776, protesting Americans had pleaded that they were entitled to the rights of Englishmen, as expressed in the British constitution, and particularly in the Bill of Rights of 1689. But Jefferson's Declaration of Independence had abandoned this tack ... and had carried the American cause into the misty debatable land of an abstract liberty, equality, fraternity.


Unlike Kirk, Professor Daniel Boorstin, librarian of Congress emeritus and a distinguished scholar of American history, sees no difference between the earlier American arguments and the one set forth on July 4, 1776. The "object" of the Revolution, he writes, "as Thomas Jefferson expounded it in his Summary View of the Rights of British America (1774) ... and then in the Declaration of Independence, was to vindicate the rights of Englishmen under the British Constitution." Of course, the refusal to accept the Declaratory Act could be understood to mean no more than that the Americans rejected second-class citizenship and that they would have been satisfied with the same kind of representative government enjoyed by the subjects of the Crown in the United Kingdom.

    Let us then turn to Jefferson's Summary View, to see whether there is continuity or difference in the authoritative arguments of Americans in the Revolution. Above all, let us inquire into the relationship, in Jefferson's understanding, between the rights of Englishmen under the British constitution and the rights of man under the "laws of nature and of nature's God." Let us see how and why, according to Jefferson, the rights of the people were recognized by the British constitution. And let us consider how, or whether, such recognition led to Lincoln's conclusions concerning the role of free elections as a means of deciding who should rule in a popular republic. Is it really possible for ballots to replace bullets in the presence of fundamental differences concerning the purposes of the regime?


* * *


    The Summary View of the Rights of British America was published in August 1774, nearly a year before the beginning of the American Revolution. It was prepared for a meeting of the Virginia revolutionary convention, which was in fact the House of Burgesses, reelected and reconvened after its dissolution by the royal governor. Jefferson hoped that the convention would instruct the Virginia delegates to the Continental Congress to press for the adoption of the Summary View by that Congress. It was never actually adopted by either legislative body, being deemed too radical for that moment. But it was ordered to be published, was widely circulated in England as well as America, and came to be regarded, deservedly, as the classic expression of the American cause on the eve of the Revolution. It almost certainly was a major reason that Jefferson was chosen as a draftsman (with John Dickinson) of the Declaration of the Causes and Necessity of Taking Up Arms in July 1775 and a year later of the Declaration of Independence. Indeed, the latter can be regarded as essentially an epitome of the Summary View.

    The Summary View is in the form of a resolution of the Continental Congress, expressing the opinion of all thirteen colonies. We shall speak of it, however, as Jefferson's work and as an expression of Jefferson's views, however much they may, at the time, have been unofficial. Over time, these became the quintessentially American views, which is why Abraham Lincoln looked to Jefferson more than to anyone else for his understanding of the American Revolution.

In addressing the king on behalf of the "colonies," Jefferson refers to the latter, from time to time, as "States." As we shall see, the Summary View embodies a Whig view of the British constitution that was in certain respects so radical that its validity would have been conceded by very few Englishmen of Jefferson's generation, and certainly by none of those who were advising the king. Those conservatives who today look to Burke's celebration, in his writings on the French Revolution, of the eighteenth-century British constitution (and of the quasi-feudal social order it encompassed) will not recognize it in Jefferson's "American whig" version. Reading the Summary View today, one can sense that the Fourth of July is just around the corner.

    It is true that the American demands upon the king are portrayed by Jefferson as authorized by British constitutional law and precedents. But Jefferson's understanding of such law and precedents is distinctively Jeffersonian. At no point is the authority of the British constitution derived from prescriptive or historic right, as distinct from, and opposed to, natural right. Right is prescriptive only insofar as the right that is inherited is itself natural in its genesis and its reason. It is also true that the stated (or prudent) objective of the address is reconciliation. But the tone and manner in which it speaks to the king is one of independence.

    The Summary View begins by complaining to the king that the "humble application to his imperial throne" made in the past by "his States," acting individually, has gone unanswered. Now the states' "joint address" will be "penned in the language of truth, and divested of those expressions of servility, which would persuade his Majesty that we are asking favors, and not rights." At the beginning of a great tradition, Jefferson thus adopts the language of Union and Liberty (or Equality) as one and inseparable. The king must realize, he says, that it is rights, not favors, for which the "states of British America" ask recognition and redress:


[T]his his Majesty will think we have reason to expect when he reflects that he is no more than the chief officer of the people, appointed by the laws, and circumscribed with definite powers, to assist in working the great engine of government, erected for their use, and, consequently subject to their superintendence.


To speak of the "chief officer of the people" suggests a republic rather than a monarchy and an office more like America's constitutional presidency than a hereditary monarch. We must also wonder at the bland euphemism in the phrase "appointed by the laws." The laws do not appoint. The laws can only prescribe how someone is to be appointed. Jefferson is here evading rhetorically the fact that this "popular" official is not appointed (or elected) by those for whose sake his office is said to exist.

    But how can this hereditary monarch be "subject to [the] superintendence" of the people, when he is neither elected nor removable by any peaceful constitutional process? Jefferson's logic seems to proceed first by attributing (hypothetical) legitimacy to the British constitution and then by recognizing no other ground of legitimacy than the sovereignty of the people. Ergo: the British constitution is based upon the sovereignty of the people! Jefferson seems to be saying that in principle, if not in fact, Britain is a republic under the forms of a monarchy.

    Here, according to Jefferson, is how the people had exercised their "superintendence" over their kings during the constitutional crises of the seventeenth century.


A family of Princes was then on the British throne, whose treasonable crimes against their people, brought on them, afterwards, the exertion of those sacred and sovereign rights of punishment, reserved in the hands of the people for cases of extreme necessity, and judged by the constitution unsafe to be delegated to any other judicature.


In 1774, writing as a Whig in the British tradition, Jefferson assumed that it was the natural right of revolution—which here meant plainly the right to kill the king when the people judged him to have become a tyrant—that acted as the inducement to constitutionally correct behavior. Certainly at that time there was no idea on the political horizon of an election of the "chief officer of the people" by the people as the means of assuring that he serve their interests. Not until his inaugural address in 1801 would Jefferson see the right of free election as the normal and peaceable fruit of the right of revolution. But by Jefferson's theory, the right of revolution would forever underlie the right of free election and would supply a compelling reason why governments ought to have such elections as authentic expressions, not only of the people's will, but also of those rights that are the authority for the people's will. That is to say, the wholesome fear of the people by governments would also be a wholesome fear informing the majority in its dealings with minorities.

    In Lincoln's first inaugural address, threescore years after Jefferson's, Lincoln would be very careful, while denying any validity to the alleged constitutional right of secession, to insist on recognizing the natural fight of revolution. He would concede that there could be occasions on which a minority might be justified in having recourse to that right (as he had once argued on behalf of the Texans' revolt against Mexican misgovernment) if there was a real threat to deprive them of any of their fundamental rights. He would be at great pains, however, to argue that this was not the case in 1861. In the absence of any such threat, the right of revolution gave no moral sanction to secession. On the contrary, the right of revolution, being a right of the people, supported his election by the people. In such a case, the right of revolution became the right of the majority to suppress the rebellion against its legitimate authority.


* * *


    Expounding the rights of British Americans in their relationship to the rights of those in the mother country, Jefferson reminds the king


that our ancestors, before their emigration to America, were the free inhabitants of the British dominions in Europe, and possessed a right, which nature has given all men, of departing from the country in which chance, not choice, has placed them, of going in quest of new habitations, and of there establishing new societies, under such laws and regulations as to them shall seem most likely to promote public happiness.


What our ancestors had done in coming to America, Jefferson continues, was no different from what their ancestors had done before them. In emigrating to Britain,


their Saxon ancestors had, under this universal law, in like manner, left their native wilds and woods in the North of Europe, had possessed themselves of the Island of Britain, then less charged with inhabitants, and had established there that system of laws which has so long been the glory and protection of that country.


Let us notice first that the British constitution itself arose from "a right [under universal law] which nature has given all men." That right is primarily and essentially a natural right to liberty. It is a right of all men to leave the country "in which chance, not choice, has placed them." Where a man is born may be a matter of chance. Where and how he is to live, however, are (and of right ought to be) matters of choice. But they are not random choices. They are choices guided by reason. In seeking new habitations and establishing new societies, under laws that they have agreed to, men act in such manner as to them "shall seem most likely to promote public happiness." Happiness is the objective good, and therefore the rational good, at which all laws and institutions aim. This is assumed by Jefferson, here and elsewhere, no less than by Aristotle, as it was by American public opinion of the Revolutionary generation.

    A great deal has been written to the effect that because the Declaration of Independence speaks of a right to "the pursuit of happiness," rather than a right to happiness, happiness itself must be something subjective, something each individual should be free to pursue in his own idiosyncratic manner. The implication is that happiness cannot be a goal of public policy, since there is neither an agreement as to what it is nor a means of proving any one opinion on this question to be superior to any other. A free government is therefore looked upon as one that enables each individual to pursue happiness as he thinks fit to do, in as unrestrained a manner as possible. But what is idiosyncratic is private, and Jefferson speaks in the Summary View of public happiness. The Declaration itself speaks not only of the unalienable right to the pursuit of happiness, with which each individual has been endowed by his Creator, but also of the "safety and happiness" which each people collectively attempts to secure when it institutes new government. Clearly, whatever is uniquely individual in the private pursuit of happiness must be consistent with the public happiness and must fit within its framework.

    In a letter in 1819, Jefferson avowed his distrust of an "independent" judiciary as the final authority on the meaning of the Constitution. "Independence can be trusted nowhere but with the people in mass," he wrote, adding that the people "are inherently independent of all but moral law." Likewise, near the end of the Summary View, Jefferson tells the king in a most peremptory way that "The great principles of right and wrong are legible to every reader." And again: "The whole art of government consists in the art of being honest." Although Jefferson believed in safeguards against the abuse of power by the people, no less than by anyone else, he also was convinced that the people "in mass" had a greater interest than anyone else in governmental honesty. Lincoln echoed Jefferson's convictions when he asked, in his first inaugural address, "Why should there not be a patient confidence in the ultimate justice of the people?" But however independent of all earthly authorities the people may have been, they were not, according to Jefferson, independent of the "moral law." They too were to be measured against the great standards of right and wrong. Lincoln also made it clear that his confidence in the justice of the people was not unconditional but depended upon their retaining "their virtue and vigilance." One might say that concern with the virtue and vigilance of the people was of the essence of statesmanship, according to Jefferson and Lincoln. In what they understood by a "people," subordination to the "moral law" and the demands of "virtue" was implicit. The people could not promote public happiness if they did not have a due regard for virtue and the moral law in their private lives. No one ever asserted this more categorically than George Washington, in his inaugural address.


[T]he foundation of our national policy will be laid in the pure and immutable principles of private morality ... since there is no truth more thoroughly established than that there exists in the economy and course of nature an indissoluble union between virtue and happiness; between duty and advantage; between the genuine maxims of an honest and magnanimous policy and the solid rewards of public prosperity.


As in the tradition of Plato's Republic, public virtue, and therefore public happiness, is private virtue writ large.

    That the "great principles of right and wrong" were "legible to every reader" meant that they were knowable to the unassisted reason of any human being of ordinary, but uncorrupted, intelligence. Certainly they were as legible to peoples as to kings. And to repeat, there could be no idea of happiness, whether individual or public, inconsistent with virtue and the moral law. While the chance may have been greater of there being virtue in the people as a whole than in any of the parts, especially the governmental parts, it is not something guaranteed apart from the application of the political art, "the art of being honest." In a government of the people, the art of being honest must be the people's art.

(Continues...)

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Chapter 1: The Election of 1800 and the Election of 1860
Chapter 2: The Declaration of Independence, the Gettysburg Address, and the Historians
Chapter 3: The Divided American Mind on the Eve of Conflict: James Buchanan, Jefferson Davis, and Alexander Stephens Survey the Crisis
Chapter 4: The Mind of Lincoln's Inaugural and the Argument and Action of the Debate That Shaped It—I
Chapter 5: The Mind of Lincoln's Inaugural and the Argument and Action of the Debate That Shaped It—II
Chapter 6: July 4, 1861: Lincoln Tells Why the Union Must be Preserved
Chapter 7: Slavery, Secession, and State Rights: The Political Teaching of John C. Calhoun
Appendix: "The Dividing Line between Federal and Local Authority: Popular Sovereignty in the Territories"—A Commentary
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)