A New Kind of Science

Hardcover (Print)
Buy Used
Buy Used from BN.com
$26.44
(Save 41%)
Item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging.
Condition: Used – Good details
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $2.51
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 94%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (101) from $2.51   
  • New (6) from $23.97   
  • Used (95) from $2.51   

Overview

This long-awaited work from one of the world's most respected scientists presents a series of dramatic discoveries never before made public. Starting from a collection of simple computer experiments—illustrated in the book by striking computer graphics—Wolfram shows how their unexpected results force a whole new way of looking at the operation of our universe.

Wolfram uses his approach to tackle a remarkable array of fundamental problems in science: from the origin of the Second Law of thermodynamics, to the development of complexity in biology, the computational limitations of mathematics, the possibility of a truly fundamental theory of physics, and the interplay between free will and determinism.

Written with exceptional clarity, and illustrated by more than a thousand original pictures, this seminal book allows scientists and non-scientists alike to participate in what promises to be a major intellectual revolution.

About the Author:

Stephen Wolfram was born in London and educated at Eton, Oxford and Caltech. He received his PhD in theoretical physics in 1979 at the age of 20, and in the early 1980s made a series of discoveries which launched the field of complex systems research. Starting in 1986 he created Mathematica, the primary software system now used for technical computing worldwide, and the tool which made A New Kind of Science possible. Wolfram is the founder and CEO of Wolfram Research, Inc.—the world's leading technical software company.

...from a collection of simple computer experiments—illustrated in the book by striking computer graphics—Wolfram shows how their unexpected results force a whole new way of looking at the operation of our universe...

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

From Barnes & Noble
The Barnes & Noble Review
Since the 1970s, emerging discoveries about chaos, complexity, and randomness have tantalized just about everyone clued in to the intellectual currents of the age. Are these discoveries mere "toys" or harbingers of an entirely new worldview? If you were smart and wealthy enough to pursue these issues as your life work, you'd be Stephen Wolfram. And, at the end of your journey, you'd believe you'd found a gateway to an entirely new science -- one that will clear away age-old obstacles in fields ranging from cosmology to economics.

Wolfram, almost unique among contemporary scientists, has avoided publishing his findings until he could bring them together in a comprehensive treatment for both scientists and nonscientists. A New Kind of Science is that book.

Wolfram's lab is his computer (appropriate, since he made his fortune creating Mathematica calculation software for scientific research). Drawing on massive amounts of computer power, he shows that incredible complexity can arise from even the simplest systems and rules. This isn't entirely a new idea. More surprising, perhaps, Wolfram shows that the reverse is true: Order sometimes arises spontaneously out of chaos. Still not quite a revolution, but Wolfram has delved further into complexity than anyone else, identifying guiding principles that appear to have universal application in nature.

Scientists, even the most revolutionary, are people of their times. It may be that in 400 years, people will accuse Wolfram of the classic fallacy of "owning a hammer and thinking everything's a nail." But it's also possible that humanity will have 400 years of progress to look back on, thanks in no small part to his work. (Bill Camarda)

Library Journal
Galileo proclaimed that nature is written in the language of mathematics, but Wolfram would argue that it is written in the language of programs and, remarkably, simple ones at that. A scientific prodigy who earned a doctorate from Caltech at age 20, Wolfram became a Nobel-caliber researcher in the emerging field of complexity shortly thereafter only to abscond from academe and establish his own software company (which published this book). In secrecy, for over ten years, he experimented with computer graphics called cellular automata, which produce shaded images on grid patterns according to programmatic rules (973 images are reproduced here). Wolfram went on to discover that the same vastly complex images could be produced by even very simple sets of rules and argues here that dynamic and complex systems throughout nature are triggered by simple programs. Mathematical science can describe and in some cases predict phenomena but cannot truly explain why what happens happens. Underscoring his point that simplicity begets complexity, Wolfram wrote this book in mostly nontechnical language. Any informed, motivated reader can, with some effort, follow from chapter to chapter, but the work as a whole and its implications are probably understood fully by the author alone. Had this been written by a lesser scientist, many academics might have dismissed it as the work of a crank. Given its source, though, it will merit discussion for years to come. Essential for all academic libraries. [This tome is a surprise best seller on Amazon. Ed.] Gregg Sapp, Science Lib., SUNY at Albany Copyright 2002 Cahners Business Information.
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9781579550080
  • Publisher: Wolfram Media, Incorporated
  • Publication date: 5/14/2002
  • Edition description: New Edition
  • Pages: 1196
  • Sales rank: 350,794
  • Product dimensions: 8.14 (w) x 9.70 (h) x 2.47 (d)

Meet the Author

Stephen Wolfram was born in London and educated at Eton, Oxford and Caltech. He received his PhD in theoretical physics in 1979 at the age of 20, and in the early 1980s made a series of discoveries which launched the field of complex systems research. Starting in 1986 he created Mathematica, the primary software system now used for technical computing worldwide, and the tool which made A New Kind of Science possible. Wolfram is the founder and CEO of Wolfram Research, Inc.—the world's leading technical software company.
Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

A New Kind of Science


By Stephen Wolfram

Wolfram Media, Inc.
www.wolfram-media.com

Copyright © 2002 Stephen Wolfram, LLC.
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 1579550088



Chapter One


The Foundations for a
New Kind of Science


An Outline of Basic Ideas

Three centuries ago science was transformed by the dramatic new idea that rules based on mathematical equations could be used to describe the natural world. My purpose in this book is to initiate another such transformation, and to introduce a new kind of science that is based on the much more general types of rules that can be embodied in simple computer programs.

It has taken me the better part of twenty years to build the intellectual structure that is needed, but I have been amazed by its results. For what I have found is that with the new kind of science I have developed it suddenly becomes possible to make progress on a remarkable range of fundamental issues that have never successfully been addressed by any of the existing sciences before.

If theoretical science is to be possible at all, then at some level the systems it studies must follow definite rules. Yet in the past throughout the exact sciences it has usually been assumed that these rules must be ones based on traditional mathematics. But the crucial realization that led me to develop the new kind of science in this book is that there is in fact no reason to think that systems like those we see in nature should follow only such traditional mathematical rules.

Earlier in history it might have been difficult to imagine what more general types of rules could be like. But today we are surrounded by computers whose programs in effect implement a huge variety of rules. The programs we use in practice are mostly based on extremely complicated rules specifically designed to perform particular tasks. But a program can in principle follow essentially any definite set of rules. And at the core of the new kind of science that I describe in this book are discoveries I have made about programs with some of the very simplest rules that are possible.

One might have thought—as at first I certainly did—that if the rules for a program were simple then this would mean that its behavior must also be correspondingly simple. For our everyday experience in building things tends to give us the intuition that creating complexity is somehow difficult, and requires rules or plans that are themselves complex. But the pivotal discovery that I made some eighteen years ago is that in the world of programs such intuition is not even close to correct.

I did what is in a sense one of the most elementary imaginable computer experiments: I took a sequence of simple programs and then systematically ran them to see how they behaved. And what I found— to my great surprise—was that despite the simplicity of their rules, the behavior of the programs was often far from simple. Indeed, even some of the very simplest programs that I looked at had behavior that was as complex as anything I had ever seen.

It took me more than a decade to come to terms with this result, and to realize just how fundamental and far-reaching its consequences are. In retrospect there is no reason the result could not have been found centuries ago, but increasingly I have come to view it as one of the more important single discoveries in the whole history of theoretical science. For in addition to opening up vast new domains of exploration, it implies a radical rethinking of how processes in nature and elsewhere work.

Perhaps immediately most dramatic is that it yields a resolution to what has long been considered the single greatest mystery of the natural world: what secret it is that allows nature seemingly so effortlessly to produce so much that appears to us so complex.

It could have been, after all, that in the natural world we would mostly see forms like squares and circles that we consider simple. But in fact one of the most striking features of the natural world is that across a vast range of physical, biological and other systems we are continually confronted with what seems to be immense complexity. And indeed throughout most of history it has been taken almost for granted that such complexity—being so vastly greater than in the works of humans—could only be the work of a supernatural being.

But my discovery that many very simple programs produce great complexity immediately suggests a rather different explanation. For all it takes is that systems in nature operate like typical programs and then it follows that their behavior will often be complex. And the reason that such complexity is not usually seen in human artifacts is just that in building these we tend in effect to use programs that are specially chosen to give only behavior simple enough for us to be able to see that it will achieve the purposes we want.

One might have thought that with all their successes over the past few centuries the existing sciences would long ago have managed to address the issue of complexity. But in fact they have not. And indeed for the most part they have specifically defined their scope in order to avoid direct contact with it. For while their basic idea of describing behavior in terms of mathematical equations works well in cases like planetary motion where the behavior is fairly simple, it almost inevitably fails whenever the behavior is more complex. And more or less the same is true of descriptions based on ideas like natural selection in biology. But by thinking in terms of programs the new kind of science that I develop in this book is for the first time able to make meaningful statements about even immensely complex behavior.

In the existing sciences much of the emphasis over the past century or so has been on breaking systems down to find their underlying parts, then trying to analyze these parts in as much detail as possible. And particularly in physics this approach has been sufficiently successful that the basic components of everyday systems are by now completely known. But just how these components act together to produce even some of the most obvious features of the overall behavior we see has in the past remained an almost complete mystery. Within the framework of the new kind of science that I develop in this book, however, it is finally possible to address such a question.

From the tradition of the existing sciences one might expect that its answer would depend on all sorts of details, and be quite different for different types of physical, biological and other systems. But in the world of simple programs I have discovered that the same basic forms of behavior occur over and over again almost independent of underlying details. And what this suggests is that there are quite universal principles that determine overall behavior and that can be expected to apply not only to simple programs but also to systems throughout the natural world and elsewhere.

In the existing sciences whenever a phenomenon is encountered that seems complex it is taken almost for granted that the phenomenon must be the result of some underlying mechanism that is itself complex. But my discovery that simple programs can produce great complexity makes it clear that this is not in fact correct. And indeed in the later parts of this book I will show that even remarkably simple programs seem to capture the essential mechanisms responsible for all sorts of important phenomena that in the past have always seemed far too complex to allow any simple explanation.

It is not uncommon in the history of science that new ways of thinking are what finally allow longstanding issues to be addressed. But I have been amazed at just how many issues central to the foundations of the existing sciences I have been able to address by using the idea of thinking in terms of simple programs. For more than a century, for example, there has been confusion about how thermodynamic behavior arises in physics. Yet from my discoveries about simple programs I have developed a quite straightforward explanation. And in biology, my discoveries provide for the first time an explicit way to understand just how it is that so many organisms exhibit such great complexity. Indeed, I even have increasing evidence that thinking in terms of simple programs will make it possible to construct a single truly fundamental theory of physics, from which space, time, quantum mechanics and all the other known features of our universe will emerge.

When mathematics was introduced into science it provided for the first time an abstract framework in which scientific conclusions could be drawn without direct reference to physical reality. Yet despite all its development over the past few thousand years mathematics itself has continued to concentrate only on rather specific types of abstract systems—most often ones somehow derived from arithmetic or geometry. But the new kind of science that I describe in this book introduces what are in a sense much more general abstract systems, based on rules of essentially any type whatsoever.

One might have thought that such systems would be too diverse for meaningful general statements to be made about them. But the crucial idea that has allowed me to build a unified framework for the new kind of science that I describe in this book is that just as the rules for any system can be viewed as corresponding to a program, so also its behavior can be viewed as corresponding to a computation.

Traditional intuition might suggest that to do more sophisticated computations would always require more sophisticated underlying rules. But what launched the whole computer revolution is the remarkable fact that universal systems with fixed underlying rules can be built that can in effect perform any possible computation.

The threshold for such universality has however generally been assumed to be high, and to be reached only by elaborate and special systems like typical electronic computers. But one of the surprising discoveries in this book is that in fact there are systems whose rules are simple enough to describe in just one sentence that are nevertheless universal. And this immediately suggests that the phenomenon of universality is vastly more common and important—in both abstract systems and nature—than has ever been imagined before.

But on the basis of many discoveries I have been led to a still more sweeping conclusion, summarized in what I call the Principle of Computational Equivalence: that whenever one sees behavior that is not obviously simple—in essentially any system—it can be thought of as corresponding to a computation of equivalent sophistication. And this one very basic principle has a quite unprecedented array of implications for science and scientific thinking.

For a start, it immediately gives a fundamental explanation for why simple programs can show behavior that seems to us complex. For like other processes our own processes of perception and analysis can be thought of as computations. But though we might have imagined that such computations would always be vastly more sophisticated than those performed by simple programs, the Principle of Computational Equivalence implies that they are not. And it is this equivalence between us as observers and the systems that we observe that makes the behavior of such systems seem to us complex.

One can always in principle find out how a particular system will behave just by running an experiment and watching what happens. But the great historical successes of theoretical science have typically revolved around finding mathematical formulas that instead directly allow one to predict the outcome. Yet in effect this relies on being able to shortcut the computational work that the system itself performs.

And the Principle of Computational Equivalence now implies that this will normally be possible only for rather special systems with simple behavior. For other systems will tend to perform computations that are just as sophisticated as those we can do, even with all our mathematics and computers. And this means that such systems are computationally irreducible—so that in effect the only way to find their behavior is to trace each of their steps, spending about as much computational effort as the systems themselves.

So this implies that there is in a sense a fundamental limitation to theoretical science. But it also shows that there is something irreducible that can be achieved by the passage of time. And it leads to an explanation of how we as humans—even though we may follow definite underlying rules—can still in a meaningful way show free will.

One feature of many of the most important advances in science throughout history is that they show new ways in which we as humans are not special. And at some level the Principle of Computational Equivalence does this as well. For it implies that when it comes to computation—or intelligence—we are in the end no more sophisticated than all sorts of simple programs, and all sorts of systems in nature.

But from the Principle of Computational Equivalence there also emerges a new kind of unity: for across a vast range of systems, from simple programs to brains to our whole universe, the principle implies that there is a basic equivalence that makes the same fundamental phenomena occur, and allows the same basic scientific ideas and methods to be used. And it is this that is ultimately responsible for the great power of the new kind of science that I describe in this book.

 


Relations to Other Areas


Mathematics. It is usually assumed that mathematics concerns itself with the study of arbitrarily general abstract systems. But this book shows that there are actually a vast range of abstract systems based on simple programs that traditional mathematics has never considered. And because these systems are in many ways simpler in construction than most traditional systems in mathematics it is possible with appropriate methods in effect to go further in investigating them.

Some of what one finds are then just unprecedentedly clear examples of phenomena already known in modern mathematics. But one also finds some dramatic new phenomena. Most immediately obvious is a very high level of complexity in the behavior of many systems whose underlying rules are much simpler than those of most systems in standard mathematics textbooks.

And one of the consequences of this complexity is that it leads to fundamental limitations on the idea of proof that has been central to traditional mathematics. Already in the 1930s Gödel's Theorem gave some indications of such limitations. But in the past they have always seemed irrelevant to most of mathematics as it is actually practiced.

Yet what the discoveries in this book show is that this is largely just a reflection of how small the scope is of what is now considered mathematics. And indeed the core of this book can be viewed as introducing a major generalization of mathematics—with new ideas and methods, and vast new areas to be explored.

The framework I develop in this book also shows that by viewing the process of doing mathematics in fundamentally computational terms it becomes possible to address important issues about the foundations even of existing mathematics.


Physics. The traditional mathematical approach to science has historically had its great success in physics—and by now it has become almost universally assumed that any serious physical theory must be based on mathematical equations. Yet with this approach there are still many common physical phenomena about which physics has had remarkably little to say. But with the approach of thinking in terms of simple programs that I develop in this book it finally seems possible to make some dramatic progress. And indeed in the course of the book we will see that some extremely simple programs seem able to capture the essential mechanisms for a great many physical phenomena that have previously seemed completely mysterious.

Existing methods in theoretical physics tend to revolve around ideas of continuous numbers and calculus—or sometimes probability. Yet most of the systems in this book involve just simple discrete elements with definite rules. And in many ways it is the greater simplicity of this underlying structure that ultimately makes it possible to identify so many fundamentally new phenomena.

Ordinary models for physical systems are idealizations that capture some features and ignore others. And in the past what was most common was to capture certain simple numerical relationships—that could for example be represented by smooth curves. But with the new kinds of models based on simple programs that I explore in this book it becomes possible to capture all sorts of much more complex features that can only really be seen in explicit images of behavior.

In the future of physics the greatest triumph would undoubtedly be to find a truly fundamental theory for our whole universe. Yet despite occasional optimism, traditional approaches do not make this seem close at hand. But with the methods and intuition that I develop in this book there is I believe finally a serious possibility that such a theory can actually be found.


Biology. Vast amounts are now known about the details of biological organisms, but very little in the way of general theory has ever emerged. Classical areas of biology tend to treat evolution by natural selection as a foundation—leading to the notion that general observations about living systems should normally be analyzed on the basis of evolutionary history rather than abstract theories. And part of the reason for this is that traditional mathematical models have never seemed to come even close to capturing the kind of complexity we see in biology. But the discoveries in this book show that simple programs can produce a high level of complexity. And in fact it turns out that such programs can reproduce many features of biological organisms—and for example seem to capture some of the essential mechanisms through which genetic programs manage to generate the actual biological forms we see. So this means that it becomes possible to make a wide range of new models for biological systems—and potentially to see how to emulate the essence of their operation, say for medical purposes. And insofar as there are general principles for simple programs, these principles should also apply to biological organisms—making it possible to imagine constructing new kinds of general abstract theories in biology.


Social Sciences. From economics to psychology there has been a widespread if controversial assumption—no doubt from the success of the physical sciences—that solid theories must always be formulated in terms of numbers, equations and traditional mathematics. But I suspect that one will often have a much better chance of capturing fundamental mechanisms for phenomena in the social sciences by using instead the new kind of science that I develop in this book based on simple programs. No doubt there will quite quickly be all sorts of claims about applications of my ideas to the social sciences. And indeed the new intuition that emerges from this book may well almost immediately explain phenomena that have in the past seemed quite mysterious. But the very results of the book show that there will inevitably be fundamental limits to the application of scientific methods. There will be new questions formulated, but it will take time before it becomes clear when general theories are possible, and when one must instead inevitably rely on the details of judgement for specific cases.


Computer Science. Throughout its brief history computer science has focused almost exclusively on studying specific computational systems set up to perform particular tasks. But one of the core ideas of this book is to consider the more general scientific question of what arbitrary computational systems do. And much of what I have found is vastly different from what one might expect on the basis of existing computer science. For the systems traditionally studied in computer science tend to be fairly complicated in their construction—yet yield fairly simple behavior that recognizably fulfills some particular purpose. But in this book what I show is that even systems with extremely simple construction can yield behavior of immense complexity. And by thinking about this in computational terms one develops a new intuition about the very nature of computation.

One consequence is a dramatic broadening of the domain to which computational ideas can be applied—in particular to include all sorts of fundamental questions about nature and about mathematics. Another consequence is a new perspective on existing questions in computer science—particularly ones related to what ultimate resources are needed to perform general types of computational tasks.


Philosophy. At any period in history there are issues about the universe and our role in it that seem accessible only to the general arguments of philosophy. But often progress in science eventually provides a more definite context. And I believe that the new kind of science in this book will do this for a variety of issues that have been considered fundamental even since antiquity. Among them are questions about ultimate limits to knowledge, free will, the uniqueness of the human condition and the inevitability of mathematics. Much has been said over the course of philosophical history about each of these. Yet inevitably it has been informed only by current intuition about how things are supposed to work. But my discoveries in this book lead to radically new intuition. And with this intuition it turns out that one can for the first time begin to see resolutions to many longstanding issues—typically along rather different lines from those expected on the basis of traditional general arguments in philosophy.


Art. It seems so easy for nature to produce forms of great beauty. Yet in the past art has mostly just had to be content to imitate such forms. But now, with the discovery that simple programs can capture the essential mechanisms for all sorts of complex behavior in nature, one can imagine just sampling such programs to explore generalizations of the forms we see in nature. Traditional scientific intuition—and early computer art—might lead one to assume that simple programs would always produce pictures too simple and rigid to be of artistic interest. But looking through this book it becomes clear that even a program that may have extremely simple rules will often be able to generate pictures that have striking aesthetic qualities—sometimes reminiscent of nature, but often unlike anything ever seen before.


Technology. Despite all its success, there is still much that goes on in nature that seems more complex and sophisticated than anything technology has ever been able to produce. But what the discoveries in this book now show is that by using the types of rules embodied in simple programs one can capture many of the essential mechanisms of nature. And from this it becomes possible to imagine a whole new kind of technology that in effect achieves the same sophistication as nature. Experience with traditional engineering has led to the general assumption that to perform a sophisticated task requires constructing a system whose basic rules are somehow correspondingly complicated. But the discoveries in this book show that this is not the case, and that in fact extremely simple underlying rules—that might for example potentially be implemented directly at the level of atoms—are often all that is needed. My main focus in this book is on matters of basic science. But I have little doubt that within a matter of a few decades what I have done will have led to some dramatic changes in the foundations of technology—and in our basic ability to take what the universe provides and apply it for our own human purposes.

 


Some Past Initiatives


My goals in this book are sufficiently broad and fundamental that there have inevitably been previous attempts to achieve at least some of them. But without the ideas and methods of this book there have been basic issues that have eventually ended up presenting almost insuperable barriers to every major approach that has been tried.


Artificial Intelligence. When electronic computers were first invented, it was widely believed that it would not be long before they would be capable of human-like thinking. And in the 1960s the field of artificial intelligence grew up with the goal of understanding processes of human thinking and implementing them on computers. But doing this turned out to be much more difficult than expected, and after some spin-offs, little fundamental progress was made. At some level, however, the basic problem has always been to understand how the seemingly simple components in a brain can lead to all the complexities of thinking. But now finally with the framework developed in this book one potentially has a meaningful foundation for doing this. And indeed building on both theoretical and practical ideas in the book I suspect that dramatic progress will eventually be possible in creating technological systems that are capable of human-like thinking.


Artificial Life. Ever since machines have existed, people have wondered to what extent they might be able to imitate living systems. Most active from the mid-1980s to the mid-1990s, the field of artificial life concerned itself mainly with showing that computer programs could be made to emulate various features of biological systems. But normally it was assumed that the necessary programs would have to be quite complex. What the discoveries in this book show, however, is that in fact very simple programs can be sufficient. And such programs make the fundamental mechanisms for behavior clearer—and probably come much closer to what is actually happening in real biological systems.


Catastrophe Theory. Traditional mathematical models are normally based on quantities that vary continuously. Yet in nature discrete changes are often seen. Popular in the 1970s, catastrophe theory was concerned with showing that even in traditional mathematical models, certain simple discrete changes could still occur. In this book I do not start from any assumption of continuity—and the types of behavior I study tend to be vastly more complex than those in catastrophe theory.


Chaos Theory. The field of chaos theory is based on the observation that certain mathematical systems behave in a way that depends arbitrarily sensitively on the details of their initial conditions. First noticed at the end of the 1800s, this came into prominence after computer simulations in the 1960s and 1970s. Its main significance is that it implies that if any detail of the initial conditions is uncertain, then it will eventually become impossible to predict the behavior of the system. But despite some claims to the contrary in popular accounts, this fact alone does not imply that the behavior will necessarily be complex. Indeed, all that it shows is that if there is complexity in the details of the initial conditions, then this complexity will eventually appear in the large-scale behavior of the system. But if the initial conditions are simple, then there is no reason for the behavior not to be correspondingly simple. What I show in this book, however, is that even when their initial conditions are very simple there are many systems that still produce highly complex behavior. And I argue that it is this phenomenon that is for example responsible for most of the obvious complexity we see in nature.


Complexity Theory. My discoveries in the early 1980s led me to the idea that complexity could be studied as a fundamental independent phenomenon. And gradually this became quite popular. But most of the scientific work that was done ended up being based only on my earliest discoveries, and being very much within the framework of one or another of the existing sciences—with the result that it managed to make very little progress on any general and fundamental issues. One feature of the new kind of science that I describe in this book is that it finally makes possible the development of a basic understanding of the general phenomenon of complexity, and its origins.


Computational Complexity Theory. Developed mostly in the 1970s, computational complexity theory attempts to characterize how difficult certain computational tasks are to perform. Its concrete results have tended to be based on fairly specific programs with complicated structure yet rather simple behavior. The new kind of science in this book, however, explores much more general classes of programs—and in doing so begins to shed new light on various longstanding questions in computational complexity theory.


Cybernetics. In the 1940s it was thought that it might be possible to understand biological systems on the basis of analogies with electrical machines. But since essentially the only methods of analysis available were ones from traditional mathematics, very little of the complex behavior of typical biological systems was successfully captured.


Dynamical Systems Theory. A branch of mathematics that began roughly a century ago, the field of dynamical systems theory has been concerned with studying systems that evolve in time according to certain kinds of mathematical equations—and in using traditional geometrical and other mathematical methods to characterize the possible forms of behavior that such systems can produce. But what I argue in this book is that in fact the behavior of many systems is fundamentally too complex to be usefully captured in any such way.


Evolution Theory. The Darwinian theory of evolution by natural selection is often assumed to explain the complexity we see in biological systems—and in fact in recent years the theory has also increasingly been applied outside of biology. But it has never been at all clear just why this theory should imply that complexity is generated. And indeed I will argue in this book that in many respects it tends to oppose complexity. But the discoveries in the book suggest a new and quite different mechanism that I believe is in fact responsible for most of the examples of great complexity that we see in biology.


Experimental Mathematics. The idea of exploring mathematical systems by looking at data from calculations has a long history, and has gradually become more widespread with the advent of computers and Mathematica. But almost without exception, it has in the past only been applied to systems and questions that have already been investigated by other mathematical means—and that lie very much within the normal tradition of mathematics. My approach in this book, however, is to use computer experiments as a basic way to explore much more general systems—that have never arisen in traditional mathematics, and that are usually far from being accessible by existing mathematical means.


Fractal Geometry. Until recently, the only kinds of shapes widely discussed in science and mathematics were ones that are regular or smooth. But starting in the late 1970s, the field of fractal geometry emphasized the importance of nested shapes that contain arbitrarily intricate pieces, and argued that such shapes are common in nature. In this book we will encounter a fair number of systems that produce such nested shapes. But we will also find many systems that produce shapes which are much more complex, and have no nested structure.


General Systems Theory. Popular especially in the 1960s, general systems theory was concerned mainly with studying large networks of elements—often idealizing human organizations. But a complete lack of anything like the kinds of methods I use in this book made it almost impossible for any definite conclusions to emerge.


Nanotechnology. Growing rapidly since the early 1990s, the goal of nanotechnology is to implement technological systems on atomic scales. But so far nanotechnology has mostly been concerned with shrinking quite familiar mechanical and other devices. Yet what the discoveries in this book now show is that there are all sorts of systems that have much simpler structures, but that can nevertheless perform very sophisticated tasks. And some of these systems seem in many ways much more suitable for direct implementation on an atomic scale.


Nonlinear Dynamics. Mathematical equations that have the property of linearity are usually fairly easy to solve, and so have been used extensively in pure and applied science. The field of nonlinear dynamics is concerned with analyzing more complicated equations. Its greatest success has been with so-called soliton equations for which careful manipulation leads to a property similar to linearity. But the kinds of systems that I discuss in this book typically show much more complex behavior, and have no such simplifying properties.


Scientific Computing. The field of scientific computing has usually been concerned with taking traditional mathematical models—most often for various kinds of fluids and solids—and trying to implement them on computers using numerical approximation schemes. Typically it has been difficult to disentangle anything but fairly simple phenomena from effects associated with the approximations used. The kinds of models that I introduce in this book involve no approximations when implemented on computers, and thus readily allow one to recognize much more complex phenomena.


Self-Organization. In nature it is quite common to see systems that start disordered and featureless, but then spontaneously organize themselves to produce definite structures. The loosely knit field of self-organization has been concerned with understanding this phenomenon. But for the most part it has used traditional mathematical methods, and as a result has only been able to investigate the formation of fairly simple structures. With the ideas in this book, however, it becomes possible to understand how vastly more complex structures can be formed.


Statistical Mechanics. Since its development about a century ago, the branch of physics known as statistical mechanics has mostly concerned itself with understanding the average behavior of systems that consist of large numbers of gas molecules or other components. In any specific instance, such systems often behave in a complex way. But by looking at averages over many instances, statistical mechanics has usually managed to avoid such complexity. To make contact with real situations, however, it has often had to use the so-called Second Law of Thermodynamics, or Principle of Entropy Increase. But for more than a century there have been nagging difficulties in understanding the basis for this principle. With the ideas in this book, however, I believe that there is now a framework in which these can finally be resolved.


The Personal Story of the Science in This Book

I can trace the beginning of my serious interest in the kinds of scientific issues discussed in this book rather accurately to the summer of 1972, when I was twelve years old. I had bought a copy of the physics textbook on the right, and had become very curious about the process of randomization illustrated on its cover. But being far from convinced by the mathematical explanation given in the book, I decided to try to simulate the process for myself on a computer.

The computer to which I had access at that time was by modern standards a very primitive one. And as a result, I had no choice but to study a very simplified version of the process in the book. I suspected from the start that the system I constructed might be too simple to show any of the phenomena I wanted. And after much programming effort I managed to convince myself that these suspicions were correct.

Yet as it turns out, what I looked at was a particular case of one of the main kinds of systems—cellular automata—that I consider in this book. And had it not been for a largely technical point that arose from my desire to make my simulations as physically realistic as possible, it is quite possible that by 1974 I would already have discovered some of the principal phenomena that I now describe in this book.

As it was, however, I decided at that time to devote my energies to what then seemed to be the most fundamental area of science: theoretical particle physics. And over the next several years I did indeed manage to make significant progress in a few areas of particle physics and cosmology. But after a while I began to suspect that many of the most important and fundamental questions that I was encountering were quite independent of the abstruse details of these fields.

And in fact I realized that there were many related questions even about common everyday phenomena that were still completely unanswered. What for example is the fundamental origin of the complicated patterns that one sees in turbulent fluids? How are the intricate patterns of snowflakes produced? What is the basic mechanism that allows plants and animals to grow in such complex ways?

To my surprise, very little seemed to have been done on these kinds of questions. At first I thought it might be possible to make progress just by applying some of the sophisticated mathematical techniques that I had used in theoretical physics. But it soon became clear that for the phenomena I was studying, traditional mathematical results would be very difficult, if not impossible, to find.

So what could I do? It so happened that as an outgrowth of my work in physics I had in 1981 just finished developing a large software system that was in some respects a forerunner to parts of Mathematica. And at least at an intellectual level the most difficult part of the project had been designing the symbolic language on which the system was based. But in the development of this language I had seen rather clearly how just a few primitive operations that I had come up with could end up successfully covering a vast range of sophisticated computational tasks.

So I thought that perhaps I could do something similar in natural science: that there might be some appropriate primitives that I could find that would successfully capture a vast range of natural phenomena. My ideas were not so clearly formed at the time, but I believe I implicitly imagined that the way this would work is that such primitives could be used to build up computer programs that would simulate the various natural systems in which I was interested.

There were in many cases well-established mathematical models for the individual components of such systems. But two practical issues stood in the way of using these as a basis for simulations. First, the models were usually quite complicated, so that with realistic computer resources it was very difficult to include enough components for interesting phenomena to occur. And second, even if one did see such phenomena, it was almost impossible to tell whether in fact they were genuine consequences of the underlying models or were just the result of approximations made in implementing the models on a computer.

But what I realized was that at least for many of the phenomena I wanted to study, it was not crucial to use the most accurate possible models for individual components. For among other things there was evidence from nature that in many cases the details of the components did not matter much—so that for example the same complex patterns of flow occur in both air and water. And with this in mind, what I decided was that rather than starting from detailed realistic models, I would instead start from models that were somehow as simple as possible—and were easy to set up as programs on a computer.

At the outset, I did not know how this would work, and how complicated the programs I would need would have to be. And indeed when I looked at various simple programs they always seemed to yield behavior vastly simpler than any of the systems I wanted to study.

But in the summer of 1981 I did what I considered to be a fairly straightforward computer experiment to see how all programs of a particular type behaved. I had not really expected too much from this experiment. But in fact its results were so surprising and dramatic that as I gradually came to understand them, they forced me to change my whole view of science, and in the end to develop the whole intellectual structure of the new kind of science that I now describe in this book.

The picture on the right shows a reproduction of typical output from my original experiment. The graphics are primitive, but the elaborate patterns they contain were like nothing I had ever seen before. At first I did not believe that they could possibly be correct. But after a while I became convinced that they were—and I realized that I had seen a sign of a quite remarkable and unexpected phenomenon: that even from very simple programs behavior of great complexity could emerge.

But how could something as fundamental as this never have been noticed before? I searched the scientific literature, talked to many people, and found out that systems similar to the ones I was studying had been named "cellular automata" some thirty years earlier. But despite a few close approaches, nobody had ever actually tried anything quite like the type of experiment I had.

Yet I still suspected that the basic phenomenon I had seen must somehow be an obvious consequence of some known scientific principle. But while I did find that ideas from areas like chaos theory and fractal geometry helped in explaining some specific features, nothing even close to the phenomenon as a whole seemed to have ever been studied before.

My early discoveries about the behavior of cellular automata stimulated a fair amount of activity in the scientific community. And by the mid-1980s, many applications had been found in physics, biology, computer science, mathematics and elsewhere. And indeed some of the phenomena I had discovered were starting to be used as the basis for a new area of research that I called complex systems theory.

Throughout all this, however, I had continued to investigate more basic questions, and by around 1985 I was beginning to realize that what I had seen before was just a hint of something still much more dramatic and fundamental. But to understand what I was discovering was difficult, and required a major shift in intuition.

Yet I could see that there were some remarkable intellectual opportunities ahead. And my first idea was to try to organize the academic community to take advantage of them. So I started a research center and a journal, published a list of problems to attack, and worked hard to communicate the importance of the direction I was defining.

But despite growing excitement—particularly about some of the potential applications—there seemed to be very little success in breaking away from traditional methods and intuition. And after a while I realized that if there was going to be any dramatic progress made, I was the one who was going to have to make it. So I resolved to set up the best tools and infrastructure I could, and then just myself pursue as efficiently as possible the research that I thought should be done.

In the early 1980s my single greatest impediment had been the practical difficulty of doing computer experiments using the various rather low-level tools that were available. But by 1986 I had realized that with a number of new ideas I had it would be possible to build a single coherent system for doing all kinds of technical computing. And since nothing like this seemed likely to exist otherwise, I decided to build it.

The result was Mathematica.

For five years the process of building Mathematica and the company around it absorbed me. But in 1991—now no longer an academic, but instead the CEO of a successful company—I was able to return to studying the kinds of questions addressed in this book.

And equipped with Mathematica I began to try all sorts of new experiments. The results were spectacular—and within the space of a few months I had already made more new discoveries about what simple programs do than in all the previous ten years put together. My earlier work had shown me the beginnings of some unexpected and very remarkable phenomena. But now from my new experiments I began to see the full force and generality of these phenomena.

As my methodology and intuition improved, the pace of my discoveries increased still more, and within just a couple of years I had managed to take my explorations of the world of simple programs to the point where the sheer volume of factual information I had accumulated would be the envy of many long-established fields of science.

Quite early in the process I had begun to formulate several rather general principles. And the further I went, the more these principles were confirmed, and the more I realized just how strong and general they were.

When I first started at the beginning of the 1980s, my goal was mostly just to understand the phenomenon of complexity. But by the mid-1990s I had built up a whole intellectual structure that was capable of much more, and that in fact provided the foundations for what could only be considered a fundamentally new kind of science.

It was for me a most exciting time. For everywhere I turned there were huge untouched new areas that I was able to explore for the first time. Each had its own particular features. But with the overall framework I had developed I was gradually able to answer essentially all of what seemed to be the most obvious questions that I had raised.

At first I was mostly concerned with new questions that had never been particularly central to any existing areas of science. But gradually I realized that the new kind of science I was building should also provide a fundamentally new way to address basic issues in existing areas.

So around 1994 I began systematically investigating each of the various major traditional areas of science. I had long been interested in fundamental questions in many of these areas. But usually I had tended to believe most of the conventional wisdom about them. Yet when I began to study them in the context of my new kind of science I kept on seeing signs that large parts of this conventional wisdom could not be correct.

The typical issue was that there was some core problem that traditional methods or intuition had never successfully been able to address—and which the field had somehow grown to avoid. Yet over and over again I was excited to find that with my new kind of science I could suddenly begin to make great progress—even on problems that in some cases had remained unanswered for centuries.

Given the whole framework I had built, many of the things I discovered seemed in the end disarmingly simple. But to get to them often involved a remarkable amount of scientific work. For it was not enough just to be able to take a few specific technical steps. Rather, in each field, it was necessary to develop a sufficiently broad and deep understanding to be able to identify the truly essential features—that could then be rethought on the basis of my new kind of science.

Doing this certainly required experience in all sorts of different areas of science. But perhaps most crucial for me was that the process was a bit like what I have ended up doing countless times in designing Mathematica: start from elaborate technical ideas, then gradually see how to capture their essential features in something amazingly simple. And the fact that I had managed to make this work so many times in Mathematica was part of what gave me the confidence to try doing something similar in all sorts of areas of science.

Often it seemed in retrospect almost bizarre that the conclusions I ended up reaching had never been reached before. But studying the history of each field I could in many cases see how it had been led astray by the lack of some crucial piece of methodology or intuition that had now emerged in the new kind of science I had developed.

When I made my first discoveries about cellular automata in the early 1980s I suspected that I had seen the beginning of something important. But I had no idea just how important it would all ultimately turn out to be. And indeed over the past twenty years I have made more discoveries than I ever thought possible. And the new kind of science that I have spent so much effort building has seemed an ever more central and critical direction for future intellectual development.


Excerpted from A New Kind of Science by Stephen Wolfram. Copyright © 2002 by Stephen Wolfram, LLC. Excerpted by permission. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.


Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

PREFACE
THE KEY IDEAS OF A NEW KIND OF SCIENCE
1 The Foundations for a New Kind of Science
2 The Crucial Experiment
3 The World of Simple Programs
4 Systems Based on Numbers
5 Two Dimensions and Beyond
6 Starting from Randomness
7 Mechanisms in Programs and Nature
8 Implications for Everyday Systems
9 Fundamental Physics
10 Processes of Perception and Analysis
11 The Notion of Computation
12 The Principle of Computational Equivalence
NOTES ON ALL CHAPTERS
INDEX
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Average Rating 3.5
( 30 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(13)

4 Star

(6)

3 Star

(2)

2 Star

(4)

1 Star

(5)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously
See All Sort by: Showing 1 – 20 of 30 Customer Reviews
  • Anonymous

    Posted March 20, 2008

    Finally, someone with guts!

    I have not read this book. Only just heard about it and checking this site.I am just a human. Wow! I thought I was the only one who knew. Great ready humanity. It's time.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted October 31, 2006

    A Highly Sophisticated and Disciplined Study of Computational Models

    A New Kind of Science is not for the timid. To truly appreciate the research of Stephen Wolfram, it is necessary to really think about what this book has to say and what it means for contemporary science and technology. It is also necessary to read the book as actively as possible, perhaps even performing the experiments on a computer. The major tenet of NKS is that the scientific community should implement a systematic study of computational models (what Wolfram refers to as 'simple programs') for their own sake. Why? Because not only do the decepitively simple rules of these programs give rise to great complexity, deeming them quite interesting study on their own, but their behavior is of enormous consequence for pure and applied science and mathematics, as well as philosophy and the social sciences. Wolfram's style is conducive to both the general reader and the seasoned expert in computational science. He elucidates very profound concepts strikingly well, yet maintains a discipline characteristic of a scientific journal. One should not be discouraged by the massive size of the book. Much of it is composed of diagrams of the simple programs that Wolfram has studied, and the Notes at the end can stand on their own. As an enthusiastic member of the NKS community, I can highly recommend this book not only to those interested in science and mathematics, but also to those who enjoy novel philosophy and methodology.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted December 30, 2002

    A great book with practical applications

    I bought this book from Barnes Noble. Finally finished reading. Here are my two cents.____ A great book that explains how the Universe came to being. If a single thought created our Universe, certainly the thought did not take 5 days to complete. A single and simple event can, over time produce profound effects. While physicists still trying to figure out how a simple program can lead to such complexity due to the immense time involved in the iteration phase ¿ the more practical application of the book is in business of managing complexity.____ Personally, I have been designing Business Intelligence and Decision Support systems to improve Business Agility for many years. The book provides the fundamental insight to observed effects in global economy and has helped me to focus on specific architecture of businesses to enhance agility from adaptive demand forecasting to strategic enterprise management. I am sure the book can illuminate the path to new drug discovery, gene manipulation or anti-terrorism systems too. ____ I highly recommend the book to those who are designing or solving highly complex co-dependent, multi-variate, time-series systems or issues.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted January 18, 2003

    larger than it really needed to be

    I found a lot of his points very interesting. Not new in the theories, but the examples themselves. He spent FAR too much time talking about "if simple underlying rules are inputted, you will get complex irregular results". I swear, he must have put that in 5 to 10 times. I just wish he had more scientific information packed in and less pointless wandering in the book.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted November 15, 2002

    A great scientific milestone

    I am a physicist who has been always impressed by the similar behaviors of far different phenomena and the similar mathematical expressions of many physical laws (e.g., the inverse square laws). These similarities suggest unexplored counterintuitive simplicity of nature that shows up in the mysterious complexity of this world. Stephen Wolfram considers the achievements in the understanding of complexity and offers filled with fruitful analogies and concepts story. New findings usually irritate the believers in the current paradigms. The cutting edge explorations and discoveries presented in A NEW KIND OF SCIENCE will create a healing irritation and will set the stage for the science to come. This interesting and thought provoking book will sharpen your perception and will put you in a proper state of mind to comprehend the incredibly simple picture of the universe, which will be born from the new science. I vigorously recommend this five star book as an indispensable basic title for everyone's library.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted January 7, 2003

    This 13 yr. old loves it, so why shouldn't you?

    Being 13 years old, I was so bored with what my teacher was teaching me. I decided to pick up this book. I did and to my amazement I understand every thought Stephen Wolfran has. This book is not only a gateway to a new world but a place to find that you are not alone in thinking that you can change the science of, well, science. Now I am grateful for my teacher. She is the one that had me pick up this book.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted October 19, 2002

    A breath of fresh air!

    Stephen Wolfram has presented a gem to the world. I appreciate it. He writes in plain English - a novelty. It is easy to follow. The Notes provide even more food for thought for those who want to go further. For those who indeed demand even more, I suggest, "Ok, he has showed you how to do it. Now quit complaining and go do it yourself; he has been up all night!" It is a wonderful book. I am delighted that he stayed up all those long hours doing it. I recommend it enthusiastically.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted September 2, 2002

    Wolfram's Science is Not as New as He Thinks

    There is no question that Stephen Wolfram has made a contribution to scientific knowledge with his book. However, I would not characterize it as a new kind of science. The theme that runs through his book is that complexity in nature can come from simple programs that run through a large number of iterations. Recently, I gathered a broad range of information for my book "The Meaning of Life If Life is a Journey You Need Good Directions" that looks at what truths we can learn from science about reality. Based on this study, I can say that Wolfram is far from breaking new ground. Daniel C. Dennett introduced the same basic ideas in his book ¿Darwins Dangerous Idea¿ in 1995. In fact, Dennett uses as his reference Charles Darwin¿s ideas on evolution published more than 130 years ago. According to Dennett it is possible to have ¿design without intelligence¿. In other words, a simple algorithm, another word for a program, can produce complex results without the system that is running the program having any prior intention of the results that are eventually produced. In his book Wolfram wonders how science could have taken so long to see things that he now sees as being very intuitive. Dennett answers this question as well. According to Dennett it is human nature to believe that nature works the same way that humans think. Humans are the first species to have the capacity to anticipate the results of its actions. Humans can make causal connections between actions and their outcomes. According to the anthropromorphic principle humans assume that any higher power (God) that created and controls nature works under the same principles. However according to Darwin and Dennett nature is simply adapting to changes in the environment as they occur. Wolfram states science has assumed that laws of nature were complex because we experience complexity in nature. In one sense believing that their is complexity in nature gives us a sense of comfort because we assume that something must be in control of all the complexity. If we concede that everything is subject to random events and simple programs, we also have to concede that the world is a chaotic place. Wolfram further states that he has spent the better part of his life working on this book and we have to thank him for his efforts, because he has run the computer simulations and analyzed the data to provide conclusive proof that it is fact possible to have ¿design without intelligence¿. Furthermore, he has developed a set of principles that can be used by scientists, which could be characterized as a new scientific method. For example, when looking at a system try to reduce it to the simplest level possible. Without getting to the most simple level we may be incorporating assumptions in our study, which we may assume are intuitive, but once the simulations are run we see that are assumptions are not as intuitive as we thought. Wolfram¿s book is a very long book, 846 pages without the notes, and then another 350 pages of notes. All of this information is provided to document how science, nature, etc. conform to his basic concepts. However, I am surprised why Wolfram thinks that these ideas should be such a revelation. It is generally accepted by science that the universe started about 14 billion years ago simply as energy. All subsequent matter and complexity in nature flowed from this simple beginning. Thus, we have known for some time that all complexity has flowed from this original simplicity. Any laws that we develop today should only be a natural description of this evolutionary process. Anything else would be a contradiction in logic, at least to the extent that our limit capacity to understand nature would indicate.

    1 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted September 24, 2002

    This is Nobel Prize material

    I'm a mathematician who continually irritated his professors with observations that Wolfram perfectly articulates: today's mathemetics is only capable of solving simple problems, and completely incapable of dealing with complexity. Wolfram proves that today's constraint-based mathematics is irrelevant to solving the complex problems. I predict that a hundred years from now, Wolfram will be regarded as the father of that real breakthrough we've all felt was just beyond our grasp. He proves that "computational equivalence" and "universality" can be achieved with simple systems. What he doesn't do, and what terribly interests me, is push the "irreducibility" envelope. I believe a whole set of analytical tools will emerge from A NEW KIND OF SCIENCE that will stagger even Mr. Wolfram. Time will tell.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted September 27, 2002

    enchanting turbulance

    i read the above 23 reactions (v/s miezejeski), left library, soon in the mix of a major intersection which had lost power; an enchantingly fluid, nearly divine turbulance of silent interplay, a superimposition of cat in box. i live very near police & fire stations (my insurance is low by the way); there were no calls/alarms out this particular evening. in scientific method there were certainly no theoreticians,academicians, nor artists passing through the intersection. my father, james o davis, had been head of ORNL in the late 40s/early 50s. we spoke often of the odd conversion of fascinating nuclear energy into preindustrial steam, rather than a direct link for instance to superconductivity. i am an artist, i paint, the starlings walk of people is at the heart of my discipline. i have taught in university. if direct links, spelbinding efficiencies unravel in nuclear/superconductivity i feel certain that the more fascinating will be the responsive posturings. it is easy satire to while all in good fun describe academicians being driven by great pleasure in listening/relistening to their own eloquently conducive thought interplay, by highly sensative defense/assention within university well beyond parallel in edward albe's working description, and by attracting eachother. theoreticians and artists are not distant. of course so much of this, the content of book, exists in the past, if not by semiotic history or crucial need then by abundant implication in the premis of wolfram. i am much more swayed by the interstices, the dynamic of a game than its record, as well by any inchoate thought in direction of a unified field upon which to play.

    0 out of 1 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted August 20, 2002

    Would have been revolutionary if published in the 1800s

    The controversy over Wolfram's A New Kind of Science is an invention of journalists (or, as one reviewer aptly put it, 'dilletantes') and others mostly outside of the scientific community who insist that no-one could possibly have the background to read and absorb Wolfram's opus well enough to critique it; surely such comments are motivated by petty professional jealousy passing for understanding. It's unfortunate that this tome was written by someone so wealthy; the wealthy have authority--even scientific authority, it would appear. Here's the effect that Wolfram's work is having on science: professional scientists, mathematicians and philosophers are now expected to weigh in at cocktail parties on Wolfram. Uninformed snap judgements about who is open-minded and who is a petty, mean-spirited calculus-mongering dinosaur will be determined on the basis of one's attitude towards Wolfram; body language will be scrutinized for signs of insincerity, or worse. Any criticism, however mild and however justified, will be characterized as stentorian; platitudinous, patronizing and self-congratulatory cautions to ignore Wolfram's habitual self-aggrandizment will be uttered to those who obviously haven't understood the master's message, whatever it is. Wolfram's text has been a bonanza for the scientific put-down artist (the individual whose chief contribution to the world is the put-down). The foregoing more or less characterizes the effect Wolfram's book is having on the scientific enterprise, aside from encouraging computer experimentation, here and there. At least the designers of Maple (a competitor of Mathematica) have had the good sense not to respond to A New Kind of Science with their own textbook on cellular automata.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted June 29, 2002

    A fresh outlook on science

    I found this book to be a fresh outlook on science. Yes, it does have a couple faults such as its enormous size and dogmatic writing...but all in all I found this a very good book. It's not afraid to break some rules. It points out that biology may be a better microscope than physics to view our world.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted July 23, 2002

    For so much fluff, a very heavy book

    I wanted to like this book, I wanted to discover in cellular automata new revolutionary concepts relating to the many subfields of biology, physics and mathematics. Instead I was forced to read hundreds of pages of Wolfram's personal opinions about what plants, humans and the universe really are. Wolfram had the making of an absolutely specatcular book on cellular automata that would have revolutionized THAT field and thus percolated into many others. Instead, he overreached his own understanding to explain things like free will based on a principle proved using assumptions and guesses. I have no problem with hubris so long as its justified; Wolfram's is not.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted July 18, 2002

    Vague, waffly and arrogant like the worst kind of burnt-out ex-genius

    Many assertions in this book are true. Most of the false ones are the ones that claim that he has understood more and deeper than everyone else: inasmuch as his observations are true they are well-known, and inasmuch as they are new they are uninteresting technical details (I don't believe I learned anything from this book, and I certainly don't mean to suggest that I consider myself the exception.) He keeps protesting that his discovery is slightly different from anything in the literature (e.g. with reference to chaos theory): he seems to have totally missed the point that the reason it's different in academic text (e.g. complexity of functions rather than his ``complexity of single computations'') is because *that's our only way to make it mathematically rigorous*. Yes, it is a slightly counterintuitive technical device, and if he had a way to make complexity of a single output rigorous, we'd probably care. But he waffles about complexity being ``intuitively obvious''. Geez, we knew that. So he's just writing 1000 pages about the brick wall that everyone else got round decades ago. Actually all those pages about himself and mind-numbing details of all possible cellular automata and what colour sweater he was wearing when he discovered his bogus Principle That's Better Than Everyone Else's Principle remind me somehow of the worst kind of undergraduate thesis. If it weren't for the hype and hubris I'd have given it 2 stars and merely said: some people will probably enjoy some pages, but I can recommend much better books for your time and money.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted July 18, 2002

    This guy has a 'document layout fetish' (tm)

    The book is beautifully put together. Everything from the graphics, the fonts and even the layout of the paragraphs all point to a nearly obsessed writer who delves into the wacky world of Getting Everything Just So(tm). <p> Seriously, this is a well written book. Yes. Wolfram's ego is large enough to sustain it. Yes, the book does not give enough credit where credit is due. And sadly, the most interesting chapter of the book (on physics) is also the shortest and most likely the weakest. It'd been spectacular if he had done some more simulations on mimicking quantum behavior, from a discrete Cellular Automata point of view, but he chickened out. <p> I am from academia, so I am sympathetic to those who claim that Wolfram ignores established research. Its true, he does. But this does not lessen the strength of the contents of this book. <p> If he had taken a bit more care in citing established research, I am sure that'd have smoothed over much of the negative reaction from the established people. In a way, its understandable. If your only job is to have your journal entry cited by others in other journal entries, then it hurts like heck to have some one else take claim for what you have done. <p> Ultimately, he will be ignored by the established scientists, but that won't matter very much. Popularized science, still IS science. Even away from a research lab.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted May 21, 2002

    A Power in Simplicity, But not Matter

    Wolfram¿s magnum opus is extremely brilliant and absolutely fascinating. Or at least I can say this about the parts of the book which seem to interest me the most: the Notes, in 349 pages of (overly) small print, and the invaluable Index, as well as certain figures. The Notes remind me not a little of the unique sweep and precision of the eminent physicist John Archibald Wheeler in his books, perhaps because of the sheer energy and power of their minds, and the overspreading play of ideas and interests. The rest of the volume, or main text, has the virtue of simplicity, and is essential as an overview of the author¿s research and ¿new science¿, and for its explanations and direct assertions, but it is on the whole of inferior interest and value. ||| Even if Wolfram¿s key beliefs, those which underlie his system, should turn out to be wrong, his book will long remain what it is now: enormously challenging, useful, and informative, and a masterpiece of interdisciplinary scholarship and universal thought and creativity. ||| The main value of his methods and system, I believe, is in their correction of certain inexcusable neglects in theoretical and experimental physics, and science generally. The argument of the book, however, exaggerates the absolute importance of these methods and principles, and of certain kinds of natural phenomena and behavior; and, in a cardinal error, it mistakes them for physical reality itself. Ironically, however, Wolfram has not sufficiently generalized his ideas, for they can be put in a still higher, or given a more fundamental, form, and extended to a larger class of related things. He has wrongly grasped and praised the mere tail of a great animal, of which science itself, until now, has held a shank. ||| ¿Worthless,¿ Freeman Dyson is quoted by Wired magazine as saying about Wolfram¿s ¿A New Kind of Science¿. That, too, is a possibility! And `lovable as the man is¿, it is a tempting assessment of his self-trumpeting masterpiece. In my remarks above, I was trying to be generous in defiance of precisely that temptation. ||| On the other hand, it is very unhealthy to stay up all night, as Wolfram describes himself as doing, in his monologic book. For one thing, it can blight one¿s view of mankind on topside. For another, if my may speak here as a neuroscientist, it can warp one¿s judgment, or ability to distinguish between reality and a fantasy, a thing in one¿s mind and that greater thing ¿ that most stubborn fact ¿ which is the world itself. ||| Cellular automata are so simple that they can suggest everything in nothing, and act as a powerful generator of illusions, particularly because of their novelty of form and behavior. The physicist who is first confronted with the mechanism of life must be knocked head over heels in a fool¿s amazement. And Stephen Wolfram suffered, and clearly suffers even now, from the additional, most grievous and unkind, disadvantage of having been an infant prodigy. ||| There is power in simplicity, but not matter. Cellular automata may be a valuable new formalizing tool in physics, added to mathematics, but I would bet all the world that they are not the world.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted May 21, 2002

    A big disappointment.

    I have been expecting this book for quite sometime. I was truly impressed by the author's biography and his claims on his web page saying that this book brings 'a whole new way of looking at the operation of our universe.' I have read the first 400 pages of this book. Conceptually, there is nothing novel in it. Even before this book, the striking similarities between nature and dynamical systems were well known (See James Gleick's Chaos). Wolfram's analysis of dynamical systems is all visual, not analytical; at the same time it is very boring to read. I think that the book is more about nice graphical representation of time evolution of some dynamical systems, than a new 'big theory.' Wolfram thinks that he should get credit about many things which he call 'grand discoveries.' But I think that his points are either trivial or wrong. As I said, I've just read the first 400 pages, but I don't think I will continue reading the rest of the book. In my opinion, don't waste your money and time with this book.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted May 30, 2002

    PhD in complex systems

    This book is more hype than delivery. If he is going to claim to produce some great new unifing theory of everything, then it should try to back it up in a more concrete manner, a more mathematical manner. If he is really the genius that he claims to be, then he should be humble and show us his greatness rather than tell us his greatness. I read half of the book and it is very poorly done and the typesetting is bad for the notes and supporting parts. I would not suggest buying and reading this book. It however will probably cause a bit of debate for several years if not thrown into the realm of science fiction.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted May 28, 2002

    A New Cure for Insomnia

    Stephen Wolfram's 'A New Kind of Science' could have used an editor. The text is highly repetitive and boring. This is an intellectually soft book. Astonishingly, the book has no bibliography. Wolfram mentions very few other scientists by name in the main text; Godel is among the few who are mentioned in the main text, in the chapter on the so-called 'Principle of Computational Equivalence,' where it is stated that thanks to Wolfram's discoveries, Godel's incompleteness theorems should no longer be seen as suprising. At long last, Wolfram has provided a context in which the incompleteness theorems appear inevitable, he writes, dismissing the work of dozens of researchers in the field of logic and recursion theory. The book is full of Biblical sounding pronouncements alerting the reader to the importance of what he is about to read; these reach a climax in the final chapter on the Principle of Computational Equivalence, which is supposed to have implications not only for physics, but for mathematics, philosophy and--one of Wolfram's favorite phrases (aside from his liberal use of the pronoun 'I')--'elsewhere'. <p> Wolfram's Principle of Computational Equivalence is stated in vague terms; attempts by several professional mathematician colleagues of mine to locate a precise statement of the principle met without success. Here is an attempt to restate the principle; it rests on the assumption that any physical process can be 'viewed as a computation'. This is ancient and goes back at least to the mechanism of the 18th Century. The Principle, as far as we could determine, is that any two physical processes that aren't 'obviously simple' are of 'equivalent complexity.' For example, the physical process of hitting a golf ball already contains within it the computational 'complexity' and 'sophistication' of your favorite universal partial function of classical recursion theory. These are vague claims; moreover, attempts to make them more precise seem to falsify them. <p> One of the difficulties rests with the interpretation of 'obviously simple', not to mention that the term 'complexity' isn't defined (it appears to be defined 'ostensively' by eyeballing the runs of numerous cellular automata), and no notion of 'equivalence' is offered. Do we throw away the Chomsky hierarchy? Programming languages recognizable by pushdown automata (Mathematica is an example of a context-free language; such languages are precisely those recognized by pushdown automata) but not by deterministic fnite-state automata are arguably less 'obviously simple' than regular languages; do we then conclude,on the basis of the Principle of Computational Equivalence, that the Chomsky Hierarchy collapses on the basis of this perceived added complexity? The principle of computational equivalence is too vague to be of scientific use; if it conflates the levels of any of the various known hierarchical classifications of computational complexity we have, then it cannot be true. No examples of physical systems of 'equivalent computational sophistication' are presented, even though it is asserted that systems which represent 'universal' computational processes abound in nature. <p> Wolfram might argue that I just don't get it; I argue that he just didn't state it, and this is a systemic problem with this intellectually soft book. Wolfram appears not to want to dirty his hands with precise definitions and statements of his 'revolutionary' principles, and would appear to want to leave the enunciation and development of his new science to the next echelon of followers. <p> Nevertheless, the book can be sporadically inadvertently amusing. I recommend it as a cure for insomnia.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted May 25, 2002

    Understanding Complexity

    This is a daring, dazzling effort attempting to discover order in a seemingly chaotic universe. Wolfram's ideas for a variety of disciplines are myriad, but stem from his one fundamental theory regarding the modeling of complex systems. This is an impressive work with the potential to be revolutionary.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
See All Sort by: Showing 1 – 20 of 30 Customer Reviews

If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
Why is this product inappropriate?
Comments (optional)