Performance and Identity in the Classical World

Performance and Identity in the Classical World

by Anne Duncan
ISBN-10:
052185282X
ISBN-13:
9780521852821
Pub. Date:
01/30/2006
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
ISBN-10:
052185282X
ISBN-13:
9780521852821
Pub. Date:
01/30/2006
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Performance and Identity in the Classical World

Performance and Identity in the Classical World

by Anne Duncan
$73.99 Current price is , Original price is $73.99. You
$73.99 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores

Overview

Actors in the classical world were often viewed as frauds and impostors, capable of deliberately fabricating their identities. Conversely, they were sometimes viewed as possessed by the characters that they played, or as merely playing themselves onstage. Numerous sources reveal an uneasy fascination with actors and acting, from the writings of elite intellectuals (philosophers, orators, biographers, historians) to the abundant theatrical anecdotes that can be read as a body of "popular performance theory." This study examines these sources, along with dramatic texts and addresses the issue of impersonation, from the late fifth century BCE to the early Roman Empire.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780521852821
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Publication date: 01/30/2006
Pages: 252
Product dimensions: 6.30(w) x 9.21(h) x 0.83(d)

About the Author

Anne Duncan is assistant professor of Classics in the Department of Languages and Literatures at Arizona State University. She has published articles on Greek and Roman comedy, Greek tragedy, and English Renaissance drama.

Read an Excerpt

Performance and Identity in the Classical World
Cambridge University Press
052185282X - Performance and Identity in the Classical World - by Anne Duncan
Excerpt



INTRODUCTION

THE HYPOCRITICAL SELF

FOR A BOOK THAT IS FILLED WITH ANECDOTES, IT SEEMS APPROPRIATE to begin with an anecdote of my own, and so here it is.

Like many children, I was afraid of clowns. I remember the moment vividly when, as a seven-year-old, I was finally able to articulate the basis of this fear. My grandparents had taken my brother and me to the circus, and since we had arrived early, we were sitting and watching the roustabouts set up the equipment. A clown spotted us and approached me and my brother. As he drew closer, I was able to get a good look at him. He asked us if we wanted to be in a procession during the show with a bunch of other kids, some animals in cages, and - of course - a whole host of clowns. I said no, shrinking back into my seat. He was surprised and looked at my grandparents, asking whether I was sure I didn't want to be part of the fun procession. They smiled and said that I was shy, and the clown retreated, seeking out other children among the early-comers. But I suddenly understood my fear: the clown had a big smile painted on his face, but the real mouth underneath the painted smile wasn't smiling. Clowns could go through a whole performance without ever actually smiling, I realized. Clowns could actually be evil, and you'd never know unless you got up close. And by then it would be too late.

The uneasiness that many people have felt throughout the ages with theatrical impersonation provided the genesis of this book. The dissonance between actor and character, or actor and mask, in the case of the ancient world, has often provoked uncertainty about actors as a class of people and acting as an activity. What follows is an examination of Greek and Roman attitudes toward actors and acting, the anxieties and desires that theatrical impersonation aroused, at different moments in Greek and Roman history. Numerous Greek vase-paintings show actors holding their masks, sometimes studying them intently, sometimes carelessly dangling them from a hand; the artists often depict the actor's face and the mask as identical.1 On the other hand, there are late Roman ivory carvings of theatrical masks that carefully show the actor's eyes, lips, and teeth behind the eye-holes and mouth-hole of the mask.2 Are these images of terror, as they would have been to my seven-year-old self, or of fascination, even admiration? I mention desires, as well as anxieties; the conclusion of my circus story is that I watched the procession of exotic animals, children selected from the audience, and clowns, and despite feeling that I had narrowly escaped some horrible fate, I was envious of the children in the spotlight. I secretly wished the clown would come back and give me a second chance.

While drama enjoyed great popularity during many periods in the ancient world, theatrical impersonation was an activity that was viewed with a great deal of ambivalence at both the moral level and the practical level. On the moral level, some people questioned the ethical status of impersonation: was it essentially lying? What effect did it have on the people who engaged in it, and what effect did it have on the spectators? On the practical level, some people wondered how acting worked: was acting the use of a set of skills, or was it a submersion of the self through some mysterious process into the character(s) played?3 Both sets of questions have to do with the ontological status of the self - that is, with the effect of mimesis on identity. Both sets of questions had profound implications for the way society viewed not just actors, but all selves.

For the purposes of this study, I am defining mimesis as the act of theatrical impersonation,4 and identity as the sense of possessing a self that is an integrated whole, consistent over time and in different settings. Scholars who study the history of ideas differ about what term to use to describe the notion of identity in antiquity, though they tend to agree that a fundamental divide separates us from the ancients. Sometime between the Renaissance and the eighteenth century, the story goes, people became self-conscious, and the modern sense of self was born, now usually termed "subjectivity."5 The ancients, on the other hand, were not blessed (or cursed) with this anxious self-consciousness, and so their sense of identity was more communal, more rooted in family, clan, gender, age, and status than in a Romantic or post-Romantic sense of possessing a unique individuality.6 The philosopher Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, for example, traces four distinct stages in the development of the sense of identity of persons. She labels the unreflective, reactive people contained within Homer and other ancient literary and philosophical texts "characters"; she describes later ancients and medievals as "persons" (based on the ancient use of the term persona in both theater and law), because they played a variety of roles and were held individually accountable for their actions; she defines as "selves" the people who lived after the advent of capitalism and the social mobility (and consequent shifts in the basis of identity) it enabled; and finally, she describes self-conscious, late-capitalist, post-Romantic folk like us as "individuals."7 The literary critic Lionel Trilling has a simpler system, speaking of persons living after the early sixteenth century as having a sense of self where sincerity was the ultimate measure of value, while modern persons have a sense of self where authenticity is the ultimate measure. Persons living before the sixteenth century, he says, simply were not "individuals" in the modern sense.8 As with Rorty's history of personal identity, the distinction Trilling draws is between external and internal evaluation of the sense of self, with a historical development from external to internal - corresponding roughly to the transition between what anthropologists call "shame cultures" and "guilt cultures," and sometimes used as a code for referring to the supposedly natural and inevitable development of Protestantism.9

It should be noted that these schemas have a pronounced evolutionary aspect to them, which might make us question them.10 If we attempt to put aside the twentieth-century evolutionary model of psychic development represented by Rorty's and Trilling's theories when we look at the ancient evidence, a somewhat different picture of ancient selfhood emerges. The various media which provide our evidence for ancient conceptions of identity - literary, historical, philosophical, medical, and rhetorical texts, funerary and other inscriptions, letters, law, portrait sculpture - present rather different views of the sense of self in antiquity, depending on their target audience, level of sophistication, and degree of self-consciousness as sources. There is evidence from the ancient world that could be used to suggest the existence of a postmodern conception of subjectivity as fluid, fragmented, constructed, or contingent: Hesiod's account of the literal construction of woman in the creation of Pandora in the Works and Days, for example, or Ovid's Metamorphoses, with its interest in physical change, dissolution of ego boundaries, and instability of gender.11 The general ideal, however, was closer to what we would call a modern sense of identity rather than a postmodern sense of subjectivity, stressing consistency (over time, among different aspects of the self, and between soul and body), self-control, and unity; Ruby Blondell has recently labeled this ideal in ancient thought "harmonious homogeneity."12 Some scholars would add that the ancient sense of self was not modern in terms of its relative lack of "inwardness"; the ancients, unlike us, were not concerned with self-scrutiny.13 This seems to overstate the case; after all, one of the most famous inscriptions from the ancient world was the inscription at the Oracle of Delphi, symbolic center of the Greek world: ΓΝΩΘΙ ΣΑΥΤΟΝ, "Know thyself." This motto (or mandate) presumes the existence of a self to be known, and a capacity for inward scrutiny in order to know it. It is another expression of the ancient conception of the ideal self.

We see this ideal expressed to different degrees in different media from the ancient world. If it is possible to generalize so broadly and so diachronically about the different kinds of evidence, most ancient literature is concerned to represent personal identity as coherent, stable, and often distinctive, with a character's appearance usually matching his or her inner nature.14 Ancient histories and biographies tend to be interested in drawing the moral character of their subjects, which is usually seen as developing through childhood and more or less fixed and coherent by adulthood.15 Philosophical writings on identity are the most prescriptive of all ancient sources, and they overwhelmingly depict the goal of a coherent, stable, integrated self subjected to reason.16 Ancient medical texts treat identity as consisting purely of the basic social categories of sex and age, with each category requiring a certain balance of temperature and moisture, or a certain balance of the humors.17 Rhetorical texts are exceedingly concerned to depict identity as coherent and stable, and therefore predictable and legally responsible, as are legal texts.18 Epideictic rhetoric too focuses on the praiseworthy individual, and in this resembles biography.19 Funerary inscriptions speak to a sense of personal identity informed by the broadest social categories - class, status, age, gender, ethnicity, familial relationships - but occasionally, they provide a glimpse of the dead person's sense of him- or herself beyond these broad categories.20 Letters are coming under scholarly scrutiny now for what they reveal about new ways of imagining identity in relation to other people: the letter can replace the physical presence of the correspondent; correspondence can create "imagined communities," to borrow Benedict Anderson's phrase; the self authoring the letter is highly aware of its own self-presentation and willing to present different personas to different correspondents.21 And portrait sculpture in the ancient world shows a fascinating mix of descriptive and proscriptive elements which could be taken to indicate a sense of identity as constructed, but which in fact indicates the same focus on moral character and role modeling that we see in ancient biography.22

Most sources from the ancient world, then, point - in both a descriptive and a proscriptive way - to a sense (an ideal) of personal identity as the possession of a stable, coherent, integrated self where appearance matches essence. A conception of identity as fluid or constructed, in particular, was something the ancients often attributed to actors, and not admiringly. For these reasons, I use the term "identity" rather than "subjectivity," because I am emphasizing the ancients' investment in the concept. We will see that there are places and moments and people in the ancient world who challenge this sense of identity as stable and coherent, just as there are others who reaffirm it. These challenges to the ideal were often made by the actor, whose occupation - pretending to be a variety of fictional selves - could be seen to call personal identity into question. Lucian relates an anecdote in his discussion of pantomime (On Dance) in which a barbarian saw a pantomime actor laying out the masks of the five characters he was about to play in his performance. The barbarian exclaimed, "My friend, I didn't realize that although you have one body, you have many souls!" ("ἐλελήθεις," ἔφη, "ὦ βέλτιστε, σῶμα μὲν τοῦτο ἕν, πολλὰς δὲ τὰς ψυχὰς ἔχων"; De salt. 66.) The joke in this anecdote is that the barbarian (naively? mock-naively?) assumes that the actor, like everyone else, should have one soul for his one body; his reaction, displaced onto a foreign, uncultured "other," is actually the voice of Greek and Roman ideology: bodies and souls are distinct, but they should match each other. Lucian's anecdote could be taken as one ancient definition of identity.

Thus it makes sense to begin a discussion of acting and identity with the body. The body is the most obvious candidate for the source of a sense of identity, whether identity is defined by the qualities of integrity, coherence, continuity, consciousness, or use of language. It is our first world as infants, and it can serve as a metaphorical map for all other bounded systems.23 The body thus seems to present a reasonable ground for an essential, stable identity, and in particular, the ground of a sexed identity. If the body is the ground of an essential identity, it may be assumed to reflect that identity; we see this assumption at work in the ancient "science" of physiognomy, for example, which claimed to read a person's inner nature by examining his or her body.24 Yet many problems arise with this assumption.25 The body can harbor an inner nature that diverges from its outward form; the body can misrepresent its inner nature, whether through clothing, adornment, cosmetics, disguise, deformation, or a host of other means. The body, in this mindset, can lie.26 One of the earliest examples of this concept in literature is Paris in the Iliad.27 Hector comments on the discrepancy between Paris' looks and his behavior after Paris shrinks from battle with Menelaus:

Δύσπαρι, εἶδος ἄριστε, γυναιμανὲς ἠπεροπευτά,
αἴθ ᾽᾽ ὄφελες ἄγονός τ ᾽᾽ ἔμεναι ἄγαμóς τ ᾽᾽ ἀπολέσθαι.
{καί κε τὸ βουλοίμην, καί κεν πολὺ κέρδιον ἦεν}
ἢ οὕτω λώβην τ ᾽᾽ ἔμεναι καὶ ἐπόψιον ἄλλων.
ἦ που καγχαλóωσι κάρη κομóωντες Ἀχαιοί,
φάντες ἀριστῆα πρόμον ἔμμεναι, οὕνεκα καλὸν
εἶδος ἔπ ᾽᾽, ἀλλ ᾽᾽ οὐκ ἔστι βίη φρεσὶν οὐδέ τις ἀλκή.

Evil Paris, beautiful, woman-crazy, deceiving,
would that you had never been born, or been killed unmarried.
Truly I would have wished it, and it would have been much better
than for you to be a disgrace in this way and viewed with suspicion by others.
Surely the long-haired Achaeans laugh out loud
thinking you are our foremost man, because you are beautiful;
but there is no strength in your breast, nor any courage.

(Iliad 3.39-45)

At the very beginning of the Greek (and Western) literary tradition, a central character displays the ominous consequences of a mismatch between appearance and inner nature: Paris looks like a brave warrior, but he acts like a coward - with fatal results for his people. Paris' mismatch between appearance and inner nature is seen by his brother not merely as an unfortunate example of cognitive dissonance, but as "deceiving" (ἠπεροπευτά); it is a moral problem. Already at the beginning of recorded Greek thought, we see the concept of the body as the basis of personal identity, and with it, the moral ideal of the body - that is, appearance - matching the inner nature. In Paris' case, these concepts are honored in the breach.

The body of the warrior is what makes battle possible; the body of the actor is what makes drama possible. In fact, drama has been called both "the adventure of the human body" and "the misadventure of the human body."28 It is the capacity of the body to "lie" - to appear other than what it "really" is - that enables mimesis to occur. Acting, not surprisingly, has thus aroused a great deal of anxiety throughout its history in people who oppose "lying" and wish appearance and reality to match exactly; they see the actor as a deceiver, pretending to be who he or she is not. Yet paradoxically, the inability of the actor's body to disappear entirely behind or into the character's costume has also proved to be a source of uneasiness. Jonas Barish, discussing the antitheatrical prejudice in D. H. Lawrence's The Lost Girl, puts his critical finger on one source of this uneasiness. Lawrence's novel is set during the period in the early twentieth century when movies were becoming popular enough to draw audiences away from traditional theater. Barish summarizes people's preference for movies in Lawrence's novel:

In short, the very element of confrontation between performer and spectator that creates excitement in the theater, the human fire that attracts Alvina [the novel's protagonist] to the actors, disturbs her townspeople, who prefer not to be hotly scorched. It requires the onlooker to take account of another human being, distinct from himself, with a prickly otherness that can never be entirely soothing, as the image on the screen can be soothing, over whose unresisting flicker the watcher may pour without hindrance whatever he will of his own feelings...If Alvina is right, audiences sense this underlying self-assertion on the part of the players, and though exhilarated by it, find it alarming.29

At a fundamental level, theater is a confrontation between the actor and the spectator. No matter how well the actor plays the role, the spectator retains a sort of awkward awareness of the actor's "otherness," his or her body beneath and behind the costume.30 Even in a theatrical tradition that uses full-head masks and full-body costumes, like ancient Greece, this confrontation between the audience and the actor's "underlying self-assertion" can produce uneasiness in some spectators.

Another reason for that uneasiness may be the way in which theater makes the socialization process of a given society apparent and transparent. A society pressures its members to conform to norms of gender, class, age, and status, but makes its pressures seem to be the workings of a natural and inevitable development;31 a play, on the other hand, shows actors reproducing those norms through conscious study and imitation. Gender norms are one especially interesting and transparent case of this necessary display. Karen Bassi, building on Judith Butler's theory of gender as only performance,32 argues that "theater is precisely the place where the political regulations and disciplinary practices that produce an ostensibly coherent gender are effectively placed in view."33 This is especially so in plays that address violations of gender norms, such as cross-dressing, or in theatrical traditions (ancient Greece and Rome, Elizabethan England) that use male actors to play female characters. If, as Rorty maintains, the ancients' sense of identity was much more confined to a sense of occupying a particular position within a series of broad categories - age, class, status, ethnicity, as well as gender - then we can generalize Bassi's observation a bit: theater is the place where the political regulations and disciplinary practices that produce an ostensibly coherent identity are placed in view. This effect of theatrical impersonation gets at one large component of the antitheatrical response in antiquity: it is motivated by a fear of upward social mobility, which theater is seen as somehow enabling. Trilling argues that the development of the concept of sincerity in the early sixteenth century was motivated by a rise in social mobility, which in turn produced anxieties about people from the lower orders dissembling or flattering their way up the social ladder; thus the character of the "villain" was born - originally the villein, or serf.34 But earlier ages and other cultures also fretted about social mobility, including Athens and Rome. The chapters that follow will have much to say about this anxiety.

A third reason for the spectator's uneasiness with theatrical impersonation is the "deception" practiced by the actor. I place "deception" in quotation marks because, as Anne Ubersfeld notes (herself quoting O. Mannoni), "the theatrical illusion is an illusion: no one is fooled."35 Yet the pretense required by acting has disturbed some spectators nonetheless, supposedly from the time of Solon and Thespis onwards. The story Plutarch tells is that Solon watched a performance by Thespis, the first actor:

μετὰ δὲ τὴν θέαν προσαγορεύσας αὐτὸν ἠρώτησεν εἰ τοσούτων ἐναντίον οὐκ αἰσχύνεται τηλικαῦτα ψευδόμενος. φήσαντος δὲ τοῦ Θέσπιδος μὴ δεινὸν εἶναι τὸ μετὰ παιδιᾶς λέγειν τὰ τοιαῦτα καὶ πράσσειν, σφόδρα τῇ βακτηρίᾳ τὴν γῆν ὁ Σόλων πατάξας· 'Ταχὺ μέντοι τὴν παιδιάν, ᾽᾽ ἔφη, 'ταύτην ἐπαινοῦντες οὕτω καὶ τιμῶντες εὑρήσομεν ἐν τοῖς συμβολαίοις. ᾽᾽

After the show [Solon] went to speak to Thespis and asked him if he was not ashamed to tell all those lies in front of such a crowd of people. Thespis replied that there was no harm in talking and acting like this in play. Solon thumped his stick heavily on the ground. "Yes, but it won't be long," he said, "if we hold this sort of 'play' in such high esteem, before it rears its head in our contractual engagements too."

(Vit. Sol. 29)




© Cambridge University Press

Table of Contents

Introduction: the hypocritical self; 1. Drag queens and in-betweens: Agathon and the mimetic body; 2. Demosthenes vs Aeschines: the rhetoric of sincerity; 3. The fraud and the flatterer: images of actors in the comic state; 4. Infamous performers: comic actors and female prostitutes in Rome; 5. The actor's freedom: Roscius and the slave actor at Rome; 6. Extreme mimesis: the spectacle in the Empire.
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews