Planning, Proposing and Presenting Science Effectively: A Guide for Graduate Students and Researchers in the Behavioral Sciences and Biology / Edition 2

Hardcover (Print)
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $90.49
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 11%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (7) from $90.49   
  • New (5) from $90.49   
  • Used (2) from $0.00   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$90.49
Seller since 2008

Feedback rating:

(169)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
0521826470 BRAND NEW NEVER USED IN STOCK 125,000+ HAPPY CUSTOMERS SHIP EVERY DAY WITH FREE TRACKING NUMBER

Ships from: fallbrook, CA

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$94.96
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(0)

Condition: New
2006 Hardcover Brand new book. Fast shipping form our UK warehouse in eco-friendly packaging. Fast, efficient and friendly customer service. Please note that this item is being ... sent from United Kingdom, allow 4-14 days for delivery. All the orders are shipped same or next working day. Fast and friendly customer service. *****PLEASE NOTE: This item is shipping from an authorized seller in Europe. In the event that a return is necessary, you will be able to return your item within the US. To learn more about our European sellers and policies see the BookQuest FAQ section***** Read more Show Less

Ships from: Hemel Hempstead, United Kingdom

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
  • Express, 48 States
  • Express (AK, HI)
$94.96
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(0)

Condition: New
2006 Hardcover Brand new book. Fast shipping form our UK warehouse in eco-friendly packaging. Fast, efficient and friendly customer service. Please note that this item is being ... sent from United Kingdom, allow 4-14 days for delivery. All the orders are shipped same or next working day. Fast and friendly customer service. *****PLEASE NOTE: This item is shipping from an authorized seller in Europe. In the event that a return is necessary, you will be able to return your item within the US. To learn more about our European sellers and policies see the BookQuest FAQ section***** Read more Show Less

Ships from: Hemel Hempstead, United Kingdom

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
  • Express, 48 States
  • Express (AK, HI)
$215.00
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(136)

Condition: New
Brand new.

Ships from: acton, MA

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$221.12
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(257)

Condition: New
Brand New Item.

Ships from: Chatham, NJ

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
  • Express, 48 States
  • Express (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Close
Sort by

Overview

This concise guide to planning, writing, and presenting research, especially in biology and behavioral ecology, is intended for students of all levels. The guidelines apply equally to independent projects for introductory courses, directed research-study projects, and undergraduate senior theses, as well as to master's theses, doctoral dissertations, and research aimed at publication. Guides the reader through a discussion of the nature of scientific research, how to plan research, and obtain funding, Discusses writing a research proposal, whether for a formal proposal for thesis research to be written by a graduate student, or for a research proposal for a funding agency such as the National Science Foundation (using the Dissertation Improvement Grant format as a specific example), Deals with writing a research project such as a graduate thesis, or a manuscript for publication in a research journal, Gives advice and guidelines for presenting the results of research at research seminars and scientific meetings, and also provides useful tips on preparing abstracts and posters for scientific meetings, Shows how to write an effective c.v, Gives tips on how to write clearly, common abbreviations (including Latin phrases), and difficult inflections, as well as other issues.
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780521826471
  • Publisher: Cambridge University Press
  • Publication date: 8/31/2006
  • Edition description: REV
  • Edition number: 2
  • Pages: 240
  • Product dimensions: 5.98 (w) x 8.98 (h) x 0.67 (d)

Meet the Author

Jack P. Hailman is Professor Emeritus of Zoology at the University of Wisconsin-Madison, and Research Associate of Archbold Biological Station in Florida. His research focuses on the behavior of birds.

Karen B. Strier is Professor of Anthropology at the University of Wisconsin, Madison. She has recently been elected to the National Academy of Sciences, USA. Her research focuses on primate behavioral ecology and conservation.

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

Planning, Proposing, and Presenting Science Effectively
Cambridge University Press
978-0-521-82647-1 - Planning, Proposing, and Presenting Science Effectively - by Jack P. Hailman, Karen B. Strier
Excerpt



I   How to plan research


    Scientific epistemology
     Science as process and product
     Deduction and prediction
     Observation and data
     Comparison and decision
     Induction and model
     Uniqueness of models
     Some consequences of the uniqueness
     Models: hypothesis, theory, law
     Roles of the individual investigator
     Is natural history really science?


    Planning research
     Finding a problem
     Formulating a model
     Devising testable predictions
     Comparative studies
     Interrelationship between field and laboratory
     Other aspects of planning research
     Implementing the plan




The great tragedy of Science – the slaying of a beautiful hypothesis by an ugly fact.

Thomas Henry Huxley (1825–95)

Success in science, as in most complex endeavors, depends partly on preparednessand planning. The three Persian princes of Serendip notwithstanding, a great truth is found in the aphorism that chance favors the prepared mind. No mere chapter could constitute a complete guide to planning research. This one attempts to cover the main points common to most projects. We begin with a background sketch of epistemology: how science as a whole works and the roles of individual investigators. That introduction provides a framework for discussing specific issues of planning research. Subsequent chapters deal with some of the major steps of doing science (e.g. how to write a grant proposal and how to communicate the results of research) that ensue after good planning.

SCIENTIFIC EPISTEMOLOGY

In order to plan research effectively, the investigator should understand how his or her activities fit into the endeavor of science as a whole. Some explanations of the “scientific method” confound epistemology – how we accumulate knowledge and understanding through science – with specific research activities of the individual investigator. This section attempts to disentangle the two by sketching the “big picture” first and then showing where the practicing scientist fits in.

Science as process and product

One can conceive of science as a cycle of activities and results based on procedures that are often referred to as the “hypothetico-deductive method.” This method evaluates a hypothesis (more generally, a model) of how the world might work and deduces consequences that must be true if the world does actually work in the way posited. One can then check the real world to see whether these predicted consequences are verifiably true. The process is cyclical because if the consequences cannot be verified, then a new hypothesis (model) must be tried. Even if the predicted consequences can be verified, however, that result might be coincidence. Therefore, one strives to deduce new predictions from the same hypothesis and test these as well. The cycle, which we call here the epistemological cycle, can be represented schematically as in Figure 1.

Figure 1.1 A schematic representation of the epistemological cycle

Image not available in HTML version


Figure 1 uses some simple conventions of illustration. Boxes, which are labeled in FULL CAPS, represent statements that can be written down: products of the processes. Arrows, which are labeled in lower case, represent processes that yield the statements in the boxes to which they point. Furthermore, each arrow originates at a statement and points to another statement, so as to show the sequence of steps in the process of science. As the diagram represents a cycle, we can scrutinize its parts beginning at any arbitrary place and then return to that place by completing the cycle. The practicing scientist, however, usually enters the cycle at one of two places: creating (or revising) a model from data at hand, or drawing testable predictions from an existing model. We begin discussion at the latter point, assuming that a model of some natural phenomenon already exists.

Deduction and prediction

Deduction is a type of reasoning that in logic leads from a set of premises to a conclusion. In science, the logical premises constitute the model, which is a speculation of how things might work in nature, and the logical conclusion is a specific prediction that is testable by observation. One could also say that a deduction is the result of the process of deducing, but that use would give two meanings to the same word, so we restrict “deduction” to the process itself.

Some writers encapsulate the deductive process as reasoning from generalities to particulars, but we think of it as a rearrangement of knowledge. In the terminology of logic, deductive reasoning extracts from a set of premises (the MODEL of Figure 1) one or more conclusions (the PREDICTION of Figure 1). No new knowledge appears in the prediction: everything in the prediction is already inherent in the model. The deductive process simply isolates part of the model or isolates several parts and then combines them. Consider a simple example:

MODEL: the earth rotates on its axis, spinning counterclockwise when viewed from above the North Pole.

From this model, one can deduce the prediction that the sun (and the other stars, for that matter) should rise above the eastern horizon, travel across the sky, and set in the west. The model of course embeds some hidden assumptions, such as all these celestial bodies being fixed in space relative to the earth. Almost all models have implicit assumptions, and failing to recognize them could lead to problems in reasoning. The prediction deduced can be written down and checked empirically, which means that one uses the process of observation, including formal measurement, to see whether the predictions match reality as we view it.

Deduction is at heart a stipulated set of rules for assuring this relationship between model and prediction: if the model is true, then the prediction deduced from it must also be true. The rules take many forms, the oldest of which is the Aristotelian syllogism. In its commonest form, the syllogism produces a conclusion (prediction of scientific epistemology) from two premises (together making the model in epistemological terms). For example:

PREMISE 1 (part of model):  If only Jack drives the van
PREMISE 2 (part of model):  And if the van is on a field trip
CONCLUSION (prediction):  Then Jack is on a field trip

Of course, science does not depend upon syllogistic reasoning, which is full of pitfalls because of the inherent imprecision of language. For example, consider this syllogism: unicorns all have horns (premise 1), and this animal has a horn (premise 2); therefore, this animal must be a unicorn (conclusion). The logical error in that syllogism is termed a fallacy of affirmation and is common in reasoning with language; just because A implies B (if it is a unicorn, it has horns) does not necessarily mean that B implies A (if it has horns, it is a unicorn). The error leads to apparent substantiation that unicorns exist. Anyone can see through the problem in a simple syllogism like this one, but much reasoning from scientific models is similarly linguistic in nature and so entails all the dangers of language itself.

Linguistic reasoning does not have to be in syllogistic form, as was demonstrated by Bertrand Russell. For example, it is possible to draw a conclusion from only one premise:

PREMISE:     If a horse is an animal
CONCLUSION:  Then a horse's head is an animal's head

Most scientific deduction is basically mathematical in nature, and, conversely, most mathematics taught in secondary schools is deductive in nature – Euclidian geometry and algebra, for example. Simple algebraic deduction can even be written in syllogistic form:

PREMISE 1:    If x+y=6
PREMISE 2:    And if y=4
CONCLUSION:  Then x=2

The deductive logic underlying the earlier example concerning the rotation of the earth on its axis was geometric.

The bridge between linguistic reasoning and mathematics is symbolic logic. Many such logic systems have been devised from different starting points, and in most cases different systems are easily shown to be equivalent. That is, given the same set of premises (together, the model of Figure 1), deduction by the rules of any given system leads validly to the same conclusion (the prediction of Figure 1). Boolean algebra is a form of symbolic logic that stands sort of midway between linguistic reasoning and traditional mathematics. The Boolean system uses the linguistic-like operators and, or, not, if, then, and except to relate variables such as propositions. Formal set theory is even more mathematical-like, using symbols for operators. All systems of deduction have in common the key property: if the premises (model) are true, then the conclusion (prediction) deduced from them is true, assuming that the deductive process scrupulously followed the rules of the system.

Observation and data

Observation in Figure 1 is the process that leads to data. “Observation” might seem a restrictive term, connoting merely noting visually what an animal is doing or some other aspect of the world. Nevertheless, we use “observation” as a general term to include all ways in which human senses are extended by instruments to record data. Ultimately, the investigator observes: for example, observes a dial or digital display on an instrument, or observes sound spectrograms made from tape recordings. Thus, observation in Figure 1 means any sensing and recording process that leads to data that can be written down or otherwise represented in hard copy.

The term “observation” might also be applied to the data produced by observing. In order to avoid confusion, we restrict our use of “observation” to the process and use “data” to describe the results of that process.

You might already have considered the question of why the arrow representing the observation process in Figure 1 points from PREDICTION, it being obvious why it points to DATA. The arrow originates at PREDICTION because the prediction specifies what kinds of data need to be observed. The prediction states what must be the case if the model is true, and the data show whether or not the prediction is upheld in the real world. Data that have nothing to do with the prediction might be an informative sidelight to a particular investigator's activities, but they have no direct bearing on the empirical test of the model. Nevertheless, observation with no particular model in mind can produce data that ultimately lead to a hypothesis. We have said that the investigator usually enters the epistemological cycle with a model to be tested or with data (often from the literature) for generating or revising hypotheses, so entering the scientific cycle through simple observation without starting predictions is an exception.

The word “experiment” does not appear in Figure 1. We have avoided that term because it tends to connote a carefully controlled laboratory environment in which every attempt is made to control extraneous variables that could influence the data. Some of biology – and especially the behavioral ecology practiced by the authors – involves mainly field studies. In some cases field studies also involve formal experiments, but in many cases they do not.

No fundamental difference exists, in terms of epistemology, between a laboratory experiment and field observations. Each approach to gathering data relevant to a prediction has its advantages and disadvantages. Laboratory experiments usually provide considerable control over extraneous variables that could influence the results, but the laboratory environment may produce artifacts. Field studies may be more natural and realistic, but generally they exercise little control over extraneous variables that could influence results. Both laboratory experiments and field observations play a role in research and can provide a particularly powerful approach when used in concert.

Comparison and decision

Sometimes, explanations of scientific epistemology fail to be explicit about the process of comparing the data observed with the prediction deduced from the model. This step is crucial to the workings of science, however, because it is not always evident whether the data are in agreement with a prediction. Extraneous factors always act upon any aspect of biology under observation, even in carefully controlled laboratory experiments.

As with deduction and observation, the term “comparison” could be applied to both the process and the results of that process. In order to avoid confusion, we use the word “comparison” to refer only to the process. The results of the process constitute the “decision” (regardless of whether the results fit the prediction).

The process of comparison commonly uses statistical methods for comparing data with predicted results. For example, a model might predict that older animals of some species tend to dominate younger animals. The data could show that this predicted relationship is an imperfect one, so the question becomes whether dominance structure is unrelated to age or is influenced by age as predicted or by some other age-associated traits. The investigator would probably employ some appropriate statistical test to see whether dominance relations were random or non-random with respect to age.

The comparison between data observed and the prediction deduced from the model yields a DECISION. Ideally, the decision is simply whether the data fit the prediction, but things do not always turn out so nicely. One may decide that it is impossible to tell whether a match exists. A common outcome of the process of comparison is that some expected difference is not statistically reliable, and yet a trend in the predicted direction is noticeable. Therefore, the difference could be real but not established by the data, either because extraneous variables unduly influenced the data (as commonly occurs in field studies) or because the sample size was insufficient to provide statistical reliability. In such cases, the main recourse is to gather better data, either with improved control over extraneous variables or with larger samples.

Yet another way in which comparison between predictions and data can fail to yield an unambiguous decision about the model is when some predictions are supported and others are not. Any validly deduced prediction that is rejected by empirical data falsifies the model, but when the deductive chain is not tight and other predictions are consistent with data, researchers sometimes refer to “partial confirmation” of the model. This situation usually suggests that the model is not quite right but has merit that could be improved by modifications based on careful scrutiny, without having to “go back to the drawing board.”

Induction and model

The decision resulting from comparison between data observed and the prediction deduced from the model dictate the next step in doing science. As noted earlier, three kinds of decisions are possible: (1) the data do not resolve the question because they are inadequate or conflicting, (2) the data do not match the prediction, or (3) the data confirm the prediction. In the first case, if the data are not sufficient, then nothing can be done except to go back and gather data adequate to the task. On the other hand, if the results testing different predictions conflict, then the model is probably not quite right and needs to be modified.

Suppose the data show unambiguously that the prediction cannot be correct: the data are simply not as predicted if the model is true. Only one explanation of this situation exists: the model is false. We say in science that the data reject the model (because they do not match the prediction deduced from the model). In this case, if one is to explain the phenomenon under investigation, it is necessary to produce a new model, or at least revise the old one, and then proceed with making and testing new predictions.

The creative process of proposing how nature works involves induction. Induction is sometimes characterized as reasoning from particulars to generalities, but that catchphrase seems vague and in any case may not always apply. We prefer to think of induction as a cluster of very complicated creative processes in which the thinker identifies possible patterns from available facts and proposes causal relationships that might explain the patterns.

No rules for creative induction exist, and the many books written on the subject seem to agree that induction is not one but many complex mental processes that find a pattern where none was recognized previously. Most of the famous models of science have come from people who reflected on disparate empirical data and somehow united them into a coherent framework. For example, Charles Darwin realized that the traits of parents and their offspring tend to be similar (genetic inheritance was not yet understood), that more offspring are born than survive to reproduce themselves, and that survival probably depends at least partly on the traits of the individual. From these empirically verifiable facts, Darwin reasoned correctly that if the survival traits are heritable, then evolution must occur: his model of natural selection. To recount another famous example, Danish physicist Niels Bohr mused over the emission spectra of elements. When one burns a substance, it emits light of specific wavelengths, the combination of wavelengths being unique to every different element. From a vast storehouse of emission spectra accumulated by empirical scientists, Bohr conceived of his atomic model of a positively charged nucleus surrounded by negatively charged electrons of different energy levels.

The examples from Darwin and Bohr are what historian of science Thomas Kuhn has called “paradigm shifts” or “revolutions”: whole reorganizations of thinking in a given area of science. Kuhn first believed that progress in scientific understanding was completely dependent upon such revolutions but later came to realize that stepwise revision of models also moved science forward (see Kuhn 1996). An entire spectrum exists from minor honing of models through substantial revisions and generalizations to major shifts in paradigms, and all have their place in the progress of science. Few practicing scientists will bring forth revolutionary new ways of viewing some natural phenomenon, but each scientist should strive to keep an open mind and induce new, viable ways of uniting disparate facts through induction.

Uniqueness of models

Because induction is a type of creativity, scientific models that result from it are unique to their creators. This assertion is controversial, but most apparent exceptions to the asserted uniqueness turn out not to be exceptions at all. The whole issue is somewhat tangential to the main point of devising or revising models, but the notion of uniqueness is important in emphasizing the creative process of induction. Therefore, we pause to consider several apparent exceptions that help to illuminate the nature of both the inductive process and the models that result from it.





© Cambridge University Press
Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Preface vii

1 How to plan research 1

Scientific epistemology 2

Planning research 17

2 How to write a research proposal 34

Format 36

Criteria for evaluation 38

Feedback 41

Proposal content 43

The submission process 60

The review process 61

What to do while waiting for a decision 62

3 How to write a research report 64

Front matter 66

Body of the report 71

End matter 77

References 78

Tables and figures 89

Submission and review 95

4 How to present research 108

Research seminars 110

Audiovisual aids 118

Talks at scientific meetings 136

Posters at scientific meetings 143

5 How to write a curriculum vitae 149

Personal information 151

Education 153

Honors, awards, and similar recognitions 155

Grants 157

Publications 158

Professional talks 160

Teaching 161

Miscellaneous optional information 162

Appendixes 165

A How to write clearly 165

Generalities 168

The three primary rules 170

Structure 171

Numbers 174

Abbreviations and animal names 178

Using signs, symbols, and marks 182

Difficult inflections 185

Problematic pairs 188

Using a word processor 194

A final suggestion 202

B Ethics considerations 203

Planning research 204

Proposing research 208

Presenting research 210

Presenting scientific credentials 214

Final comments 215

Further reading 216

Index 220

Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)