Reference and Description: The Case against Two-Dimensionalism

Overview

In this book, Scott Soames defends the revolution in philosophy led by Saul Kripke, Hilary Putnam, and David Kaplan against attack from those wishing to revive descriptivism in the philosophy of language, internalism in the philosophy of mind, and conceptualism in the foundations of modality. Soames explains how, in the last twenty-five years, this attack on the anti-descriptivist revolution has coalesced around a technical development called two-dimensional modal logic that seeks to reinterpret the Kripkean ...
See more details below
Available through our Marketplace sellers.
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (9) from $9.81   
  • New (4) from $55.57   
  • Used (5) from $9.81   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$55.57
Seller since 2005

Feedback rating:

(807)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
2004 Hardcover New in new dust jacket. Tracking provided on most orders.

Ships from: Grand Rapids, MI

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
  • Express, 48 States
  • Express (AK, HI)
$55.57
Seller since 2005

Feedback rating:

(807)

Condition: New
2004 Hardcover New Tracking provided on most orders.

Ships from: Grand Rapids, MI

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
  • Express, 48 States
  • Express (AK, HI)
$87.21
Seller since 2011

Feedback rating:

(7)

Condition: New
2004 Hardcover New Book New and in stock. 11/29/2004. *****PLEASE NOTE: This item is shipping from an authorized seller in Europe. In the event that a return is necessary, you ... will be able to return your item within the US. To learn more about our European sellers and policies see the BookQuest FAQ section***** Read more Show Less

Ships from: Morden, United Kingdom

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$145.00
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(164)

Condition: New
Brand new.

Ships from: acton, MA

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Close
Sort by
Reference and Description: The Case against Two-Dimensionalism

Available on NOOK devices and apps  
  • NOOK Devices
  • Samsung Galaxy Tab 4 NOOK
  • NOOK HD/HD+ Tablet
  • NOOK
  • NOOK Color
  • NOOK Tablet
  • Tablet/Phone
  • NOOK for Windows 8 Tablet
  • NOOK for iOS
  • NOOK for Android
  • NOOK Kids for iPad
  • PC/Mac
  • NOOK for Windows 8
  • NOOK for PC
  • NOOK for Mac

Want a NOOK? Explore Now

NOOK Book (eBook - Course Book)
$17.49
BN.com price
(Save 43%)$30.95 List Price

Overview

In this book, Scott Soames defends the revolution in philosophy led by Saul Kripke, Hilary Putnam, and David Kaplan against attack from those wishing to revive descriptivism in the philosophy of language, internalism in the philosophy of mind, and conceptualism in the foundations of modality. Soames explains how, in the last twenty-five years, this attack on the anti-descriptivist revolution has coalesced around a technical development called two-dimensional modal logic that seeks to reinterpret the Kripkean categories of the necessary aposteriori and the contingent apriori in ways that drain them of their far-reaching philosophical significance.

Arguing against this reinterpretation, Soames shows how the descriptivist revival has been aided by puzzles and problems ushered in by the anti-descriptivist revolution, as well as by certain errors and missteps in the anti-descriptivist classics themselves. Reference and Description sorts through all this, assesses and consolidates the genuine legacy of Kripke and Kaplan, and launches a thorough and devastating critique of the two-dimensionalist revival of descriptivism. Through it all, Soames attempts to provide the outlines of a lasting, nondescriptivist perspective on meaning, and a nonconceptualist understanding of modality.

About the Author:
Scott Soames, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Southern California

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

From the Publisher

"A text of this scope and care is a must for any program supporting philosophy of language and mind."--Choice
Choice
A text of this scope and care is a must for any program supporting philosophy of language and mind.
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780691121000
  • Publisher: Princeton University Press
  • Publication date: 11/29/2004
  • Pages: 384
  • Product dimensions: 6.16 (w) x 9.46 (h) x 1.14 (d)

Meet the Author

Scott Soames, formerly Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University, is now Professor of Philosophy at the University of Southern California. He is the author of "Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volumes 1 and 2" (Princeton), "Beyond Rigidity", and "Understanding Truth".

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

Reference and Description

The Case against Two-Dimensionalism
By Scott Soames

Princeton University Press

Copyright © 2004 Princeton University Press
All right reserved.




Chapter One

THE TRADITIONAL DESCRIPTIVIST PICTURE

The modern discussion of reference begins with the reaction of Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell to an initially attractive but overly simple conception of meaning and reference. The conception is based on the observation that the most important feature of language is our ability to use it to represent the world. Different sentences represent the world as being different ways, and to sincerely accept, or assertively utter, a sentence is to believe, or assert, that the world is the way the sentence represents it to be. The reason sentences are representational in this way is that they are made up of words and phrases that stand for objects and the properties we take them to have-physical objects, people, ideas, institutions, shapes, sizes, colors, locations, relations, and the rest. What it is for language to be meaningful is for it to have this representational capacity. But if meaning is essentially representational, it would seem that the meaning of any word or phrase should be just what it represents, or stands for. In short, the meaning of an expression is the thing it refers to; and the meaning of a sentence is determined by the words that make it up.

Although attractive, and even undeniable in its broad outlines, this picture gives rise to puzzles in particular cases thatled Frege and Russell to suggest significant modifications. In "On Sense and Reference," Frege considered an instance of the general problem posed by the observation that substitution of coreferential terms in a sentence sometimes changes meaning. For example, in each of the following cases he would contend that the (a) sentence differs in meaning from the (b) sentence, even though they differ only in the substitution of terms that designate the same individual.

1a. The first Postmaster General of the United States was the author of Poor Richard's Almanac

b. The first Postmaster General of the United States was the first Postmaster General of the United States.

2a. Benjamin Franklin was the first Postmaster General of the United States.

b. Benjamin Franklin was Benjamin Franklin.

3a. Ruth Marcus is Ruth Barcan.

b. Ruth Marcus is Ruth Marcus.

In each case, this contention is supported by three facts: (i) a person can understand both sentences, and so know what they mean, without taking them to mean the same thing, or to have the same truth value; (ii) a person who assertively uttered the (a) sentence typically would be deemed to have said more, and conveyed more information, than someone who assertively uttered the (b) sentence; and (iii) the (a) and (b) sentences would standardly be used in belief ascriptions, x believes that S, to report different beliefs with potentially different truth values. If, on this basis, one agrees that the (a) sentences differ in meaning from the (b) sentences, then one must reject either T1, T2, or T3.

T1. The meaning of a genuinely referring expression is its referent.

T2. Both singular definite descriptions-i.e., expressions of the form the so and so-and ordinary proper names-e.g., Benjamin Franklin, Ruth Barcan, and Ruth Marcus-are genuinely referring expressions.

T3. The meaning of a sentence, of the sort illustrated by 1-3, is a function of its grammatical structure together with the meanings of its parts; in these sentences, substitution of expressions with the same meaning doesn't change meaning.

Whereas Frege rejected T1, Russell rejected T2. However, both agreed that the meaning of an ordinary proper name is not its bearer, and the meaning of a singular definite description is not the unique object that it denotes.

According to Frege, ordinary proper names and singular definite descriptions are terms that purport to refer to unique individuals. However, the meaning, or sense, of such an expression is never identical with its referent; instead, it is something that determines reference. For example, the meaning, or sense, of the description the even prime number is something like the property of being both an even number and prime (and being unique in this); its referent is whatever has this property-the number 2. Although different singular terms with the same sense must have the same referents, terms with the same referents may have different senses. This explains the difference in meaning between the (a) and (b) sentences in (1) and (2). The explanation is extended to the sentences in (3) by Frege's contention that, like descriptions, ordinary proper names have senses that determine, but are distinct from, their referents. This is, of course, consistent with there being certain contrasts between names and descriptions. One such contrast is that most ordinary names are grammatically simple, and so, unlike descriptions, their senses are not determined by the senses of their grammatically significant parts. Because of this, it is common for different speakers to use the same name to refer to the same object, even though they associate it with different properties, or senses. Although Frege doesn't dwell on this, the illustrations he provides support the contention that he regarded the sense of a proper name n, as used by a speaker s at a time t, to be the same as that of some description the D associated with n by s at t. Thus, he may be seen as adopting T4.

T4. An ordinary proper name, n, as used by a speaker s at a time t, refers to (denotes) an object o iff o is the unique object that has the property expressed by the D (associated with n by s). When there is no such object, n remains meaningful while failing to refer to (denote) anything. In general, the meaning (for s at t) of a sentence ... n ... containing n is the same as the meaning (for s at t) of the corresponding sentence ... the D ... that arises by substituting the description for the name.

It follows from this that (3a) and (3b) differ in meaning for any speaker who associates the names Ruth Marcus and Ruth Barcan with descriptions that have different senses.

A second puzzle for the original conception of meaning and reference encompassing theses T1-T3 was Russell's problem of negative existentials, illustrated by (4).

4a. Santa Claus does not exist.

b. The largest prime number does not exist.

It would seem, prima facie, that since these sentences are true, there must be no such individuals as Santa Claus or the largest prime number, and hence that the name Santa Claus and the definite description the largest prime number do not denote, or refer to, anything. T1 and T2 then lead to the result that the name and the description don't mean anything. But surely that can't be right, since if these expressions were meaningless, then either the sentences as a whole would be meaningless, or they would both have the same degenerate meaning, consisting of the meaning of their common predicate phrase, plus a gap corresponding to their meaningless subject expressions. Neither of these alternatives is correct.

The idea behind Russell's solution is illustrated by the proposal that the (b) sentences constitute analyses of the following (a) sentences.

5a. Men are mortal.

b. [??]x (x is a man [contains] x is mortal)

The propositional function that assigns to any object o the proposition expressed by x is a man [contains] x is mortal (relative to an assignment of o to 'x') is "always true"-i.e., always yields a true proposition.

6a. Honest men exist.

b. [??]x (x is a man & x is honest)

The propositional function that assigns to any object o the proposition expressed by x is a man & x is honest (relative to an assignment of o to 'x') is "sometimes true"-i.e., sometimes yields a true proposition.

7a. Carnivorous cows don't exist.

b. ~[??]x (x is a cow & x is carnivorous)

It is not the case that the propositional function that assigns to any object o the proposition expressed by x is a cow & x is carnivorous (relative to an assignment of o to 'x') is "sometimes true"-i.e., it never yields a true proposition.

In each case, the simple subject-predicate grammatical form of the sentence differs from its more complex logical form, which is quantificational. For Russell, this means that it involves the attribution of a higher order property to a lower level property. Here, one may think of propositional functions as playing the role of properties, and of "sometimes true" and "always true" as expressing the properties of being instantiated and universally instantiated, respectively. Hence, (5) tells us that the property of being mortal-if-human is instantiated by everything, (6) that the property of being an honest man is instantiated, and (7) that the property of being both carnivorous and a cow is not instantiated.

Russell's analysis of sentences containing singular definite descriptions (phrases of the form the so and so) is rather complicated. For example, consider (8a), which he paraphrases as (8b), and analyzes as (8c).

8a. The largest prime number is even.

b. There is a number n which has the property of being both (i) even and (ii) identical with absolutely any number m iff m is a prime number which is larger than all other prime numbers.

c. [??]x [[??]y (y is a prime number & y is larger than all other prime numbers <-> y = x) & x is even]

The propositional function that assigns to any object o the proposition expressed by [??]y (y is a prime number & y is larger than all other prime numbers <-> y = x) & x is even (relative to an assignment of o to 'x') is "sometimes true"-i.e., the property of being both even and a prime number larger than all others is instantiated.

Russell's analysis of (8a)-which may be seen as equivalent to The largest prime number exists and is even-contains his analysis of the "positive existential" (9a).

9a. The largest prime number exists.

b. There is a number n which has the property of being identical with absolutely any number m iff m is a prime number which is larger than all other prime numbers.

c. [??]x [??]y [y is a prime number & y is larger than all other prime numbers <-> y = x]

The propositional function that assigns to any object o the proposition expressed by [??]y [y is a prime number & y is larger than all other prime numbers <-> y = x] (relative to an assignment of o to 'x') is "sometimes true"-i.e., the property of being a prime number larger than all others is instantiated.

With this analysis of (9a) in place, the corresponding Russellian analysis, (4c), of the negative existential (4b) is obvious.

4c. [??]x [??]y [y is a prime number & y is larger than all other prime numbers <-> y = x]

It is not the case that the propositional function that assigns to any object o the proposition expressed by [??]y [y is a prime number & y is larger than all other prime numbers <-> y = x] (relative to an assignment of o to 'x') is "sometimes true"-i.e., the property of being a prime number larger than all others is not instantiated.

For Russell, the virtue of this analysis is that (4b) is no longer seen as containing a constituent-the largest prime number-the job of which it is to refer to something (the thing which is supposed to be its meaning) which is then said not to exist. Hence there is nothing problematic, or paradoxical, in recognizing its truth.

Russell is able to give a similar analysis to (4a), since he holds that whenever one uses an ordinary proper name n, one always has some description in mind that one would be prepared to give in answer to the question Who, or what, do you mean by n? Precisely which description gives the content of the name may be expected to vary from speaker to speaker and time to time. However, whenever a name is used, there is always some description that may replace it, without changing meaning. Since Russell believes this to be true no matter what the grammatical form of the sentence, he is able to agree with Frege both in rejecting the conjunction of T1 and T2, and in accepting T4. It is their common agreement on this thesis that philosophers have in mind when they speak of the traditional Frege-Russell view of ordinary proper names.

Two further points are worth noting. First, unlike Frege, Russell never rejected the idea that the meanings of some expressions are simply their referents; rather, he believed this to be true of a small category of logically proper names-including certain demonstratives and pure indexicals-which have no other function than to refer. For example, he believed that when he said or thought to himself I am a pacifist or This is red the proposition he expressed consisted, in the first case, simply of the attribution of the property of being a pacifist to Russell himself, with no other descriptive information about him, and, in the second case, of the attribution of the property of being red to the object demonstrated, with no further attribution of descriptive properties to the object. Unfortunately, he combined his acceptance of this category of "names" with severe epistemological restrictions on the things capable of being named-essentially those about which Cartesian certainty is achievable, and mistakes are impossible. Although this made for serious difficulties, including crippling problems explaining the use of such expressions in communication, Russell's embrace of the idea of a logically proper name was historically important in the later development of nondescriptive analyses of ordinary proper names and indexicals.

Second, the traditional Frege-Russell analysis of ordinary proper names was later modified by John Searle and others to incorporate the idea that the meaning of an ordinary name for a speaker, or a community, was not given by a single description, but by an open-ended family of descriptions. On this view, the referent of the name is taken to be whatever object satisfies a sufficient number of a family of associated descriptions, and the meaning of a sentence n is F is, roughly, given by the claim The thing of which most, or a sufficient number, of the claims: it is D1, it is D2, ... are true is also F. Two alleged virtues of this variant of the Frege-Russell view are (i) that it captures the Wittgensteinian idea that the meaning of a sentence containing a name is to some degree vague and indeterminate, and (ii) that it accounts for the fact that even when D is one of the descriptions most strongly associated with n by speakers, the sentence If n exists, then n is D is not "true by definition"-sometimes, to our surprise, it can turn out to be false, and even when it is true, it often is not a necessary truth.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from Reference and Description by Scott Soames Copyright © 2004 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.
Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Ch. 1 The traditional descriptivist picture 7
Ch. 2 Attack on the traditional picture : proper names, non-descriptionality, and rigid designation 14
Ch. 3 Reasons for resistance and the strategy for descriptivist revival 35
Ch. 4 Roots of two-dimensionalism in Kaplan and Kripke 43
Ch. 5 Stalnaker's two-dimensionalist model of discourse 84
Ch. 6 The early two-dimensionalist semantics of Davies and Humberstone 106
Ch. 7 Strong and weak two-dimensionalism 133
Ch. 8 Jackson's strong two-dimensionalist program 149
Ch. 9 Chalmer's two-dimensionalist defense of zombies 194
Ch. 10 Critique of ambitious two-dimensionalism 267
Ch. 11 Positive nondescriptivism 329
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)