Securing Constitutional Democracy: The Case of Autonomy

Hardcover (Print)
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $9.93
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 80%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (7) from $9.93   
  • New (3) from $42.00   
  • Used (4) from $9.93   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$42.00
Seller since 2007

Feedback rating:

(23274)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
BRAND NEW

Ships from: Avenel, NJ

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$42.10
Seller since 2009

Feedback rating:

(9975)

Condition: New
New Book. Shipped from US within 4 to 14 business days. Established seller since 2000

Ships from: Secaucus, NJ

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$79.90
Seller since 2008

Feedback rating:

(861)

Condition: New
0226253430 Brand New. Exact book as advertised. Delivery in 4-14 business days (not calendar days). We are not able to expedite delivery.

Ships from: Romulus, MI

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Close
Sort by

Overview


Famously described by Louis Brandeis as "the most comprehensive of rights" and 'the right most valued by civilized men," the right of privacy or autonomy is more embattled during modern times than any other. Debate over its meaning, scope, and constitutional status is so widespread that it all but defines the post-1960s era of constitutional interpretation. Conservative Robert Bork called it "a loose canon in the law," while feminist Catharine MacKinnon attacked it as the “right of men to be left alone to oppress women.” Can a right with such prominent critics from across the political spectrum be grounded in constitutional law?

In this book, James Fleming responds to these controversies by arguing that the right to privacy or autonomy should be grounded in a theory of securing constitutional democracy. His framework seeks to secure the basic liberties that are preconditions for deliberative democracy—to allow citizens to deliberate about the institutions and policies of their government—as well as deliberative autonomy—to enable citizens to deliberate about the conduct of their own lives. Together, Fleming shows, these two preconditions can afford everyone the status of free and equal citizenship in our morally pluralistic constitutional democracy.

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Sanford Levinson

“In Securing Constitutional Democracy, James Fleming offers an unabashed and meticulous defense of a substantive view of judicially enforced constitutional rights at a time when the fashion in most of the legal academy is to emphasize both proceduralism and a minimal role for the courts. Fleming argues that popular approaches to constitutional analysis fall short of what he calls a ‘Constitution-perfecting theory,’ which would concern itself not only with the quality of democratic self-government but also with protecting individual autonomy. Fleming wants to supplement ‘deliberative democracy’ with an equally important ‘deliberative autonomy,’ the purpose of which is to ‘enable citizens to apply their capacity for a conception of the good in deliberating about and deciding how to live their own lives.’”--Sanford Levinson, W. St. John Garwood and W. St. John Garwood Centennial Chair, University of Texas School of Law

 

Michael C. Dorf

“In this timely and engaging book, James Fleming shows why democracy and judicial recognition of a right to individual autonomy are not antagonistic, as constitutional scholars have long fretted, but necessary complements to one another. Those who would reduce the American Constitution to a set of procedural ground rules for conducting elections, or to a collection of narrow historical compromises, lose sight of the very purpose of constitutionalism. Democracy’s point, Fleming powerfully reminds us, is to facilitate self-government, both in the sense of the polity as a whole, making decisions for the collective good, and in the sense of the individual self, making the most central decisions about how to live his or her own life.”--Michael C. Dorf, Michael I. Sovern Professor of Law, Columbia University School of Law
Jamin Raskin

Securing Constitutional Democracy is a superbly well-organized, mercifully concise, and reliably thoughtful work of legal and political philosophy. Its central thesis and contribution is its attempted ‘synthesis of modern republicanism and liberalism’ in a constitutional context. Fleming argues that our modern constitutional culture and jurisprudence are best elucidated and defended as promoting two different aspects of self-government: political and personal. This is a deeply clarifying and lucid analysis.”--Jamin Raskin, professor, American University Washington College of Law

 

Lawrence Solum

Securing Constitutional Democracy is a deep and important book that engages the most fundamental issues in constitutional theory from a fresh and refreshing perspective. Fleming’s book is simply the best elaboration of the implications of political theory in the tradition of John Rawls for the crucial issues in contemporary debates about the fundamental rights. In an era when many constitutional theorists have retreated to minimalism or formalism, it provides a sophisticated and persuasive defense of the Warren Court legacy and insists that the fundamental task of constitutional interpretation is to perfect the Constitution. Every serious student of constitutional theory needs to confront Fleming’s distinctive and original vision.”--Lawrence Solum, John E. Cribbet Professor of Law, University of Illinois College of Law

 

Law & Politics Book Review - Ronald Kahn

"Fleming has written a creative, original, and thought-provoking theoretical treatise that seeks to meld process (democratic-reinforcing) and substantive individual rights bases into an explanation of the process of constitutional decision making by courts and constitutional theorists. . . . This is one of the very best theories I have seen which seeks to make sense of the relationship between core rights and polity principles in our liberal-republican Constitution and does so by looking at hard cases."
Choice

"[Fleming] has entered the debate with a rigorous and brilliant defense of a constitutional right to personal autonomy, taking on some big guns in constitutional theory, notably Ronald Dworkin, John Hart Ely, Cass Sunstein, and Robert Bork. . . . A first-rate analysis of the principle of the unenumerated right to privacy, essential for law collections."
Harvard Law Review

"A thought-provoking alternative to current mainstream constitutional theories and justifications for judicial reviews."
Law & Politics Book Review

"Fleming has written a creative, original, and thought-provoking theoretical treatise that seeks to meld process (democratic-reinforcing) and substantive individual rights bases into an explanation of the process of constitutional decision making by courts and constitutional theorists. . . . This is one of the very best theories I have seen which seeks to make sense of the relationship between core rights and polity principles in our liberal-republican Constitution and does so by looking at hard cases."

— Ronald Kahn

Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780226253435
  • Publisher: University of Chicago Press
  • Publication date: 10/2/2006
  • Edition description: New Edition
  • Pages: 272
  • Product dimensions: 6.00 (w) x 9.00 (h) x 1.00 (d)

Meet the Author

James E. Fleming is the Leonard F. Manning Distinguished Professor of Law at Fordham University School of Law. He is coauthor of American Constitutional Interpretation.

 

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

Securing Constitutional Democracy The Case of Autonomy
By JAMES E. FLEMING
THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS Copyright © 2006 The University of Chicago
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-226-25343-5



Chapter One Securing Constitutional Democracy

The makers of our Constitution undertook to secure conditions favorable to the pursuit of happiness.... They conferred, as against the Government, the right to be let alone-the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men. - Justice Louis D. Brandeis

The Problem of Grounding Autonomy in Constitutional Law

Justice Brandeis's famous celebration of the constitutional right to privacy or autonomy as the "right to be let alone" sowed the seeds of paradox in constitutional law. The right is "the most comprehensive of rights," yet constitutional scholars and jurists have devoted more effort to narrowing, bounding, or "cabining" it than they have given any other right. It is "the right most valued by civilized men," yet scholars and jurists have repeatedly claimed either that it is trivial or that it is wild, unruly, and dangerous. Indeed, controversy over the meaning, scope, and constitutional status of this right is so widespread and durable that it all but defines the post-1960s era of constitutional adjudication. Conservative Robert H. Bork calls the right to privacy "a loose canon in the law" and its announcement in Griswold v. Connecticut (1965) the "construction of a constitutional time bomb." Feminist Catharine A. MacKinnon attacks it as "a right of men 'to be let alone' to oppress women one at a time" in private realms of sanctified isolation. Civic republican Michael J. Sandel and communitarian Mary Ann Glendon contend that theorists who defend the right to autonomy conceive persons as "lone rights-bearers" who are "unencumbered" by the bonds of community. And liberal John Hart Ely belittles "the right to be different" as an upper-middle-class right: "the right of my son to wear his hair as long as he pleases." The right to privacy or autonomy on the loose in these caricatured renditions is so unruly, dangerous, or rootless that one might wonder whether such a right can be grounded in constitutional law. Can a right with such prominent critics from across the ideological spectrum be a genuine constitutional right?

The most dramatic recent occasion for this question was Lawrence v. Texas (2003), in which a bitterly divided Supreme Court held that a law criminalizing same-sex sodomy violated a homosexual's right to privacy or autonomy. Justice Anthony Kennedy's opinion for the Court proclaimed that decisions about sexual conduct and relationships involve "'the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity and autonomy'" and that "'[b]eliefs about these matters could not define the attributes of personhood were they formed under compulsion of the state'" (quoting Planned Parenthood v. Casey [1992], which reaffirmed the central holding of Roe v. Wade [1973] that the right to privacy encompasses the right to abortion). Kennedy declared that it "demeans the lives" of homosexuals to respect the right of heterosexuals to autonomy without respecting an analogous right for them.

In dissent, Justice Antonin Scalia ridiculed this "sweet-mystery-of-life passage" from Casey and chastised the Court for "mak[ing] no effort to cabin the scope of its decision." He castigated Kennedy's opinion for putting the Court on a slippery slope leading to "the end of all morals legislation." If, said, Scalia, states may not enact their moral disapproval of homosexual sodomy, they may not in principle enact their disapproval of "bigamy, same-sex marriage, adult incest, prostitution, masturbation, adultery, fornication, bestiality, and obscenity." For him, homosexuals' intimate sexual conduct is analogous to such traditional morals offenses, not to heterosexuals' autonomy regarding intimate associations. Scalia further scolded the Court for "tak[ing] sides in the culture war, departing from its role of assuring, as neutral observer, that the democratic rules of engagement are observed."

As debated by Kennedy and Scalia, the question in Lawrence involved not merely the morality of homosexual sodomy but also important interpretive and institutional questions. The interpretive questions include: What does the Constitution mean? How are interpreters to decide what it means? What are the legitimate sources of constitutional meaning? What form of democratic government does the Constitution as a whole embody-specifically, is it a scheme of constitutional democracy that guarantees substantive rights like autonomy or, to the contrary, a scheme of majoritarian representative democracy that guarantees neutral processes for representing conflicting interests but no such substantive rights? The institutional questions include: What should be the role of courts in protecting substantive rights such as autonomy? More generally, what should be the role of courts as compared with legislatures in deciding cases implicating substantive moral disagreement in our morally pluralistic polity?

Every significant case regarding privacy or autonomy to reach the Court in the last forty years-from contraception and abortion to euthanasia and sodomy-has implicated such interpretive and institutional questions, and, at bottom, the place of these substantive liberties in our constitutional order. These cases bring out two characteristic forms of uneasiness about privacy or autonomy: the flights from protecting substantive liberties to preserving original understanding of the Constitution (narrowly conceived) and to reinforcing procedural liberties in the Constitution (to the exclusion of substantive liberties). In Lawrence and Casey, the dissenters urged taking such retreats-and thus declining to recognize rights to privacy or autonomy because they are not specifically enumerated in the text of the Constitution or are not essential to traditional procedures-but the Court resisted hankerings to do so. To secure the rights to privacy or autonomy against these flights, we must construct an overarching substantive theory that can provide a better grounding for them in our constitutional order. We need a theory that firmly connects privacy or autonomy to the substance and structures of constitutional democracy and to the roles and responsibilities of courts and legislatures in protecting constitutional norms. Meeting this challenge is the object of this book.

I ground autonomy in a theory of securing constitutional democracy, a guiding framework with two fundamental themes: first, securing the basic liberties that are preconditions for deliberative democracy, to enable citizens to apply their capacity for a conception of justice to deliberating about and judging the justice of basic institutions and social policies as well as the common good, and second, securing the basic liberties that are preconditions for deliberative autonomy, to enable citizens to apply their capacity for a conception of the good to deliberating about and deciding how to live their own lives. Together, these themes afford everyone the status of free and equal citizenship in our morally pluralistic constitutional democracy. They reflect two bedrock structures of our constitutional scheme: deliberative political and personal self-government. As against charges that rights of autonomy like those defended in Lawrence and Casey are anomalous, unruly, or rootless, I show that deliberative autonomy is rooted, along with deliberative democracy, in the language and overall design of the Constitution. Each theme has a structural role to play in securing and fostering our constitutional democracy.

My conception of the structures and design of the Constitution stems from a "constitutional constructivism," which I mean in both a methodological sense-as a method of interpreting the Constitution-and a substantive sense-as the substantive political theory that best fits and justifies our constitutional document and our underlying constitutional order. I develop such a theory by analogy to John Rawls's political constructivism, a theory he developed in Political Liberalism.

Beyond Process-Perfecting Theories to a Constitution-Perfecting Theory

I put forward a "Constitution-perfecting" theory as an alternative to the well-known "process-perfecting" theories advanced by John Hart Ely in Democracy and Distrust and Cass Sunstein in The Partial Constitution. Ely's book, published in 1980, is undoubtedly the most celebrated book in the history of constitutional theory, and Sunstein's more recent book has close affinities to it. According to their theories, the Constitution's core commitment is to democracy, and judicial review is justified principally when the processes of democracy, and thus the political decisions resulting from them, are undeserving of trust. Many find such theories alluring because of their promise that judicial review might be supportive of rather than inconsistent with democracy. Process-perfecting theories, however, are vulnerable to the criticism that they reject certain substantive liberties (such as privacy, autonomy, liberty of conscience, and freedom of association) as anomalous in our scheme, except insofar as such liberties can be recast as procedural preconditions for democracy.

Yet process-perfecting theories persist, notwithstanding such criticisms, because no one has done for "substance" what Ely has done for "process." That is, no one has developed an alternative substantive Constitution-perfecting theory-a theory that would reinforce not only the procedural liberties (those related to deliberative democracy) but also the substantive liberties (those related to deliberative autonomy) embodied in our Constitution and presupposed by our constitutional democracy-with the elegance and power of Ely's process-perfecting theory.

That is what I aspire to do in this book. I develop a Constitution-perfecting theory that secures both the substantive liberties associated with autonomy and the procedural liberties associated with democracy as fundamental, without deriving the former from the latter or, worse, failing to account for substantive liberties altogether. Unlike process theories, the book provides a firm grounding for rights to privacy and autonomy, along with liberty of conscience and freedom of association, as necessary to secure individual freedom and to promote a diverse and vigorous civil society. My theory also shows how basic liberties associated with personal autonomy, in conjunction with those related to democratic participation, fit together as a coherent scheme of basic liberties that are integral to our constitutional democracy. Finally, I show that competing theories rest on incomplete and inadequate conceptions of democracy. Throughout, I pose fresh challenges to critics who reject rights to privacy and autonomy like those recognized in Lawrence and Casey.

My defense of a Constitution-perfecting theory includes conceptions not only of what the Constitution is and how it ought to be interpreted, but also of who may authoritatively interpret it. First, as for what, constitutional constructivism conceives our Constitution as a "constitution of principle" that embodies (or aspires to embody) a coherent scheme of equal basic liberties, or fair terms of social cooperation on the basis of mutual respect and trust, for our constitutional democracy. The Constitution is not merely a "constitution of detail" that enacts a discrete list of particular rights narrowly conceived by framers and ratifiers. Nor does it simply establish a procedural framework of democracy.

Second, as regards how, constitutional constructivism conceives interpretation as the exercise of "reasoned judgment" in quest of the account that best fits and justifies the constitutional document and underlying constitutional order. Responsible interpretation is not merely exegesis of isolated clauses of the constitutional document or research into the concrete intentions or expectations of the framers and ratifiers.

Finally, with respect to who may interpret the Constitution, my theory entails a conception of the roles and responsibilities not only of courts but also of legislatures, executives, and citizens. I distinguish between the partial or judicially enforceable Constitution and the whole Constitution that is binding outside the courts on nonjudicial institutions and citizens. In other words, constitutional constructivism is a theory of the Constitution, not merely a theory of judicial review.

My theory of constitutional constructivism charts a third way between a universalist view of human rights and legal positivism. Here I follow Rawls, who advances a political constructivism that seeks to construct principles of justice that provide fair terms of social cooperation on the basis of mutual respect and trust among free and equal citizens in a morally pluralistic constitutional democracy like ours; he does not try to discover principles of justice true for all times and places. Similarly, my constitutional constructivism seeks to interpret our Constitution so as to make it the best it can be. But it is a theory of constructing our Constitution, not one that is perfectly just (unmoored by the constraints of our constitutional text, history, and structure, or by those of our practice, tradition, and culture).

In other words, constitutional constructivism is not a theory of natural law or natural rights; it does not conceive constitutional principles and rights as prepolitical and given by a prior and independent order of moral values that is binding for all times and places. Instead, it is what Frank Michelman, analyzing Rawls's political constructivism, calls an "interpretative theory" drawn from the ongoing political practice of a constitutional democracy. Constitutional constructivism draws our principles and rights from our constitutional democracy's ongoing practice, tradition, and culture. These principles are aspirational-the principles to which we as a people aspire and for which we as a people stand-and though they have a firm footing in our scheme, they may not be fully realized in our historical practices, statute books, and common law. Accordingly, constitutional constructivism recognizes that while our principles may fit and justify most of our practices, they enable us to criticize some of those practices for failing to live up to our constitutional commitments.

Overview

Part I: Constructing the Substantive Constitution

In part I (chapters 2-4) I construct a substantive Constitution-perfecting theory with two fundamental commitments: deliberative democracy and deliberative autonomy. I argue that such a theory is superior in important respects to Ely's and Sunstein's process-perfecting theories, which recast substantive liberties as procedural liberties or neglect them altogether.

THE FLIGHTS FROM SUBSTANCE IN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY

A specter is haunting constitutional theory-the specter of Lochner v. New York. In the Lochner era, the Supreme Court gave heightened judicial protection to substantive economic liberties through the Due Process Clauses. In 1937, during the constitutional revolution wrought by the New Deal, West Coast Hotel v. Parrish officially repudiated the Lochner era's special judicial protection for business interests, marking the first death of substantive due process. Nevertheless, the ghost of Lochner has haunted constitutional theory ever since, manifesting itself in charges that judges are "Lochnering" by imposing their own substantive fundamental values in the guise of interpreting the Constitution.

Charges of Lochnering have been most unrelenting with respect to Roe v. Wade, which held that the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment protects a realm of substantive personal liberty or privacy broad enough to encompass the right of a woman to decide whether to terminate a pregnancy. In a classic critique, The Wages of Crying Wolf: A Comment on Roe v. Wade, Ely argues that the Court, to avoid Lochnering, must confine itself to perfecting the processes of representative democracy, as intimated in Justice Harlan Fiske Stone's famous footnote four of United States v. Carolene Products Co.

Despite these cries, Casey reaffirmed the "central holding" of Roe instead of marking the second death of substantive due process by overruling it. In an apoplectic dissent, Justice Scalia blasted the Court for continuing to engage in Lochnering, protesting that the Court must limit itself to giving effect to the original understanding of the Constitution, narrowly conceived. Scalia made similar criticisms in his angry dissent in Lawrence.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from Securing Constitutional Democracy by JAMES E. FLEMING Copyright © 2006 by The University of Chicago. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.
Read More Show Less

Table of Contents


Acknowledgments
1. Securing Constitutional Democracy
Part I. Constructing the Substantive Constitution2. Beyond Process-Perfecting Theories of Reinforcing Representative Democracy
3. Beyond Process-Perfecting Theories of Securing Deliberative Democracy
4. An Outline for a Constitution-Perfecting Theory of Securing Constitutional Democracy
Part II. Securing Deliberative Autonomy Together with Deliberative Democracy
5. Securing Deliberative Autonomy
6. Reconceiving the Due Process Inquiry in Terms of Significance for Deliberative Autonomy: Between Scalia and Charybdis
7. Constitutional Interpretation in Circumstances of Moral Disagreement and Political Conflict
Part III. Adjusting, Preserving, and Perfecting the Scheme of Constitutional Democracy
8. Securing the Family of Basic Liberties as a Whole
9. Securing Constitutional Democracy in War and Crisis
10. Constitutional Imperfections and the Pursuit of Happy Endings: Perfecting Our Imperfect Constitution
Notes
Index
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)