The Global Limits of Competition Law

Over the last three decades, the field of antitrust law has grown increasingly prominent, and more than one hundred countries have enacted competition law statutes. As competition law expands to jurisdictions with very different economic, social, cultural, and institutional backgrounds, the debates over its usefulness have similarly evolved.

This book, the first in a new series on global competition law, critically assesses the importance of competition law, its development and modern practice, and the global limits that have emerged. This volume will be a key resource to both scholars and practitioners interested in antitrust, competition law, economics, business strategy, and administrative sciences.

1107637804
The Global Limits of Competition Law

Over the last three decades, the field of antitrust law has grown increasingly prominent, and more than one hundred countries have enacted competition law statutes. As competition law expands to jurisdictions with very different economic, social, cultural, and institutional backgrounds, the debates over its usefulness have similarly evolved.

This book, the first in a new series on global competition law, critically assesses the importance of competition law, its development and modern practice, and the global limits that have emerged. This volume will be a key resource to both scholars and practitioners interested in antitrust, competition law, economics, business strategy, and administrative sciences.

65.0 In Stock
The Global Limits of Competition Law

The Global Limits of Competition Law

The Global Limits of Competition Law

The Global Limits of Competition Law

eBook

$65.00 

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers


Overview

Over the last three decades, the field of antitrust law has grown increasingly prominent, and more than one hundred countries have enacted competition law statutes. As competition law expands to jurisdictions with very different economic, social, cultural, and institutional backgrounds, the debates over its usefulness have similarly evolved.

This book, the first in a new series on global competition law, critically assesses the importance of competition law, its development and modern practice, and the global limits that have emerged. This volume will be a key resource to both scholars and practitioners interested in antitrust, competition law, economics, business strategy, and administrative sciences.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780804782678
Publisher: Stanford Law Books
Publication date: 06/13/2012
Series: Global Competition Law and Economics
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 312
File size: 1 MB

About the Author

Ioannis Lianos is City Solicitors' Educational Trust Reader in European and Competition Law at the University College London. D. Daniel Sokol is Associate Professor of Law at the University of Florida Levin College of Law.

Read an Excerpt

The Global Limits of Competition Law


Stanford University Press

Copyright © 2012 Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-8047-7490-1


Chapter One

The Limits of Antitrust and the Chicago School Tradition

George L. Priest

The Chicago School Antitrust Tradition

As is well known, putting aside a few stray endeavors that had no abiding influence, law and economics as a field began with the work of Aaron Director and Ronald Coase centered on papers published in the Journal of Law & Economics, which began publication in the late 1950s. Looking back on those efforts, law and economics as developed by Director and Coase was not exactly ideological, but derived from what might be called a deeply held belief system that political interference in market activities interfered with freedom and reduced societal welfare. The phrase "reduced societal welfare" is a modern, technocratic concept. The opposition of Director and Coase to governmental interference in market activities was much deeper. Director was one of the founding members (along with Milton Friedman, Frank Knight, Ludwig von Mises, and George Stigler, among others) of the Mont Pelerin Society, organized by Friedrich Hayek in 1946. Hayek had published The Road to Serfdom in 1944. Following themes of The Road to Serfdom, the Mont Pelerin Society was, and to some extent still is, dedicated to the proposition that political interference with market activities is harmful to freedom—though the Society avoided a purely libertarian approach—and to broader individual and societal goals. Coase was not present at the first meeting of the Society but became a member two years later, in 1948, and at some later point, a Life Member.

The early volumes of the Journal of Law & Economics illustrate the commitment of the editors—first Director, succeeded by Coase—to the belief in the superiority of the market to political allocation of resources. The first issues contain some articles that might be regarded as economic science, but they also contain numerous articles that are essentially essays in political economy—market-oriented political economy: in volume 2 of the Journal, Hirshleifer's articles Capitalist Ethics—Tough or Soft? and The Sumptuary Manifesto, and Buchanan's Positive Economics, Welfare Economics, and Political Economy; in volume 3, Jacob Viner's The Intellectual History of Laissez Faire; in volume 4, Stigler's Private Vice and Public Virtue. Though these early volumes of the Journal do not ignore the scientific application of economic analysis, they resemble more closely a high-level journal of promarket political philosophy than a journal of economic science.

The political philosophy, however, would not entirely generate the law and economics movement; the philosophy combined with empirical work would. From the earliest issues, the editors—Director and Coase—encouraged articles of an empirical nature critical of specific governmental interventions in the market, first to complement, later to completely supplant, the essays on political economy.

Antitrust law and economic regulation were particular subjects of criticism, though articles in the Journal also addressed the effects, economic and otherwise, of the minimum wage, unionization, licensing, and even the British National Health Ser vice, among others. In the first issue of the Journal, Director published John McGee's reanalysis of the Standard Oil case, showing that the basic theory of predatory pricing underlying the Supreme Court's opinion had misunderstood the economic practices at issue entirely. Rockefeller and associates had created the Standard Oil monopoly not by predatory practices such as undercutting prices or through railroad rebates (hard to distinguish from volume discounts), but by buying out rivals, giving them a share of potential monopoly profits. Note that the point of McGee's argument is not that the Standard Oil monopoly was not a monopoly and perhaps ripe for dissolution (McGee expressly put aside that question), but rather that the economic analysis of predatory pricing adopted by the Supreme Court and in popular understanding was naive, if not idiotic. McGee's point, surely encouraged by Director, was to demonstrate that the justification given by the Court and accepted in popular opinion for governmental interference in this famous case was basically nonsense.

Most of the other articles criticizing antitrust law solicited or encouraged by Director and Coase were of this nature: Telser's study of resale price maintenance, criticizing the Supreme Court's General Electric opinion; Ward Bowman's and, later, Ken Dam's work on tying arrangements; Stigler's article on the U.S. Steel case; John Peterman's studies of Brown Shoe and International Salt. Although these articles generated substantial new learning concerning industrial practices, the underlying aim of the antitrust program was only partially scientific advance; more centrally, it was to ridicule the grounds upon which courts interfered with the marketplace.

The deep Chicago School belief in the superiority of markets and in the mistaken views of courts is reflected in the most famous article in the Journal (as well as in the history of law and economics), Ronald Coase's The Problem of Social Cost. The article is well known, but the political dimension of Coase's analysis and how his article fits within the Chicago School tradition are often unappreciated. The article is remembered today as vastly changing our understanding of the effects of legal rules. But I do not believe that it was drafted with that ambition in mind, and the article does not remotely pursue the implications for the effects of tort law or even more generally of property law, though his examples come from property law cases. That work was later accomplished by Harold Demsetz, Richard Posner, and others. Coase's article instead was directed at attacking Pigou and Pigou's purported demonstration that government, including the courts, could and should intervene in multiple markets to correct what we now call externalities. The point of the article was to show that Pigou's analysis of correcting externalities was unsupportable.

The political or ideological dimension of the Coase Theorem is often ignored. To Coase, the implication of the proposition that "in the absence of transaction costs, the assignment of liability will have no effect on the allocation of resources" is that courts and the government can do no good by interfering in markets. If government action can somehow reduce transaction costs, that may enhance welfare; otherwise, courts and the government are fooling themselves by attempting to improve upon market outcomes and should stay out. Coase's ambition was to deflate arguments for more intrusive government, not—as it happened—to revolutionize our understanding of the operation of the legal system. As a demonstration of Coase's academic program, it is not often remembered that the academic project to which Coase turned after The Problem of Social Cost was not the extension of the Coase Theorem to the analysis of legal rules, but an attack on one of the last major institutional vestiges of socialism in Western societies, the post office.

At the time, the character of Coase's insight seemed and, to some extent, still seems today an incredible demonstration of extraordinary genius. I remember thinking then, "How could a person generate such a counterintuitive idea?," and discussing the question with Dick Posner and, later, Harold Demsetz, among others. The extraordinary nature of the intuition led many to look back at Coase's earlier writings to attempt to discover possible precursors of the idea. Important in this respect was Coase's early article The Nature of the Firm—an article upon which The Limits of Antitrust importantly relies to show the difficulty courts face in evaluating contractual arrangements in comparison with firm integration, and which influences Easterbrook's other corporate work. In that article, Coase identifies the transaction costs of using the price mechanism, in contrast to direct ordering within a firm. Many, including the Nobel Prize Committee, have regarded Coase's early focus on transaction cost reduction as an explanation for the creation of a firm as at one with the recognition of the importance of transaction costs in determining the effects of legal rules.

I am skeptical of this explanation for two reasons. First, Coase's work after The Nature of the Firm did not generally focus on the implications of transaction costs. Second, there is a more direct source of the analysis in The Problem of Social Cost, consistent more broadly with Coase's and Aaron Director's beliefs. Again, the principal ambition of The Problem of Social Cost was to show that Pigou's rationalization of broad governmental, including judicial, intervention in the marketplace was both foolish and ineffectual. The Coase Theorem follows directly from a belief system that sees market transactions as inherently superior to and dominant over government interventions. If one sees a problem, an externality, that government intervention is attempting to solve, but believes deeply that the market will solve the problem more effectively, the analysis of The Problem of Social Cost becomes more apparent. Market transactions can serve to solve problems among conflicting property uses that governmental interventions cannot hope to equal. The Coase Theorem fits squarely within the Chicago School tradition that views markets as superior means of allocating resources and that, conversely, views governmental interventions as lacking analytical support and harmful in effect.

These two propositions of the Chicago School tradition—(1) that markets are superior to any form of governmental, including judicial, intervention, and (2) that judicial interventions generally have no coherent analytical basis—are central, I believe, to understanding the background of The Limits of Antitrust and the nature of the contribution of that article.

That these two propositions are central to Chicago School analysis is clear. As is well known, Aaron Director, the first editor of The Journal of Law & Economics, did not publish very much. In 1964, however, when Ronald Coase succeeded Director as editor of the Journal, Coase published as the lead article of his first issue, clearly as a tribute to his predecessor, a memorandum that Director had written in 1953 but never published, which (I presume) Coase entitled The Parity of the Economic Market Place. That article makes many points, in particular about the different treatment that U.S. liberals give to freedom of speech versus market freedom (which Coase would later pursue), but two stand out:

1. "Laissez faire has never been more than a slogan in defense of the proposition that every extension of state activity should be examined under a presumption of error;" and

2. "It is not essential to demonstrate that there is only one road to serfdom or that a particular road must inevitably lead to a specified destination [distancing himself from Hayek]. Some institutions are more flexible than others. We must choose those which minimize the risks of undesirable consequences."

These are ideas that I believe served as the basis for the extension achieved in Easterbrook's The Limits of Antitrust. Though skeptical of governmental and judicial interference, the Chicago School never advocated abandoning antitrust law in the Armentano libertarian way. The Chicago School tradition sought to constrain antitrust law—chiefly by ridiculing its excesses—but accepted antitrust enforcement as an underlying background condition of market activity.

Easterbrook's The Limits of Antitrust in the Chicago School Tradition

Easterbrook's analysis in The Limits of Antitrust builds upon the foundations of the Chicago School tradition in two important ways. First, the article extends the idea that markets are more effective than governmental intervention in correcting the impact of anticompetitive action. Thus, the article makes the important point that, with respect to what are now known as Type II prosecutorial errors—false negatives—the marketplace will correct them through enhanced competition. In contrast, again in the Director– Coase tradition, antitrust prosecution should avoid committing Type I errors—false positives—where the effects, such as with the operation of per se rules, may be irreversible.

This point does not extend as far as, but is similar in spirit to, Coase's analysis in The Problem of Social Cost. The point, however, derives from a much clearer understanding of the effects of legal rules than Coase's analysis. In The Problem of Social Cost, there were no rules resembling per se rules under the Sherman Act. Even the important article by Calabresi and Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability, did not exactly address per se rules in antitrust. They are a form of an inalienability rule, but a peculiar form. A firm cannot—as in the Coasian world—negotiate around per se rules to achieve allocative efficiency. Easterbrook saw this point and flagged the much greater danger of false positives in antitrust, a point not previously recognized in the literature.

Second, Easterbrook's article builds importantly upon the idea that courts will make erroneous judgments. Here, his distance from the Chicago School tradition is greater, which should be acknowledged. As explained, the Chicago School antitrust tradition had no doubt that judges commit errors. Indeed, in the earlier literature of the School, the term "error" does not capture the phenomenon. The Chicago School tradition held up judicial opinions in antitrust and other areas to ridicule them as laughingstocks. The underlying ambition was to delegitimize judicial and governmental interference in the market.

The Limits of Antitrust, in contrast, accepts judicial error as an underlying fact and, without ridicule, addresses, as science, the implications of inevitable judicial error for the fashioning of effective antitrust rules. This is an extraordinary extension for which Easterbrook should be given great credit, especially as it undoubtedly affected the ultimate adoption of the Chicago School approach to antitrust by the Supreme Court. Most of the articles by the Chicago School analyzing the great Supreme Court antitrust cases are hostile and dismissive of the Court's analysis. Robert Bork's important book The Antitrust Paradox was effective in providing a legal blueprint for the adoption of the Chicago School analysis but still possesses (and Bork has admitted this and has apologized for it) a sarcastic tone, largely dismissive of the ability of the Supreme Court or other courts to understand industrial organization.

The Limits of Antitrust, in contrast, explains why courts as well as businesspeople are unlikely to be able to understand complex issues in industrial organization and why—given that inability, not to be ridiculed, but to be adjusted to—the rules and methods of decision making in antitrust cases must be amended. The article then proceeds to fashion a set of filters to inform antitrust prosecution and antitrust analysis. This insight and the development of working rules for antitrust policy are achievements beyond those of the preceding Chicago School tradition. Those achievements importantly brought the Chicago School tradition within the mainstream of American legal analysis.

* * *

The lessons of The Limits of Antitrust are currently under attack. The current (2011) chief of the Antitrust Division has declared, "there is no such thing as a false positive.... I think, the more people in the bar start rejecting this idea of false positives, the better off we're going to be." And she appears to be jettisoning quite broadly the sensible filters that Easterbrook's analysis puts forth. However provocative rhetorically, her point is analytically vacant and provides no guidance on appropriate antitrust enforcement. The history of the development of Sherman Act jurisprudence since Trans-Missouri Freight has been the successive elimination of false positives. And that will remain the course of antitrust law thanks, in large part, to Easterbrook's important article, The Limits of Antitrust.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from The Global Limits of Competition Law Copyright © 2012 by Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. Excerpted by permission of Stanford University Press. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Preface vii

Contributors xi

Introduction Ioannis Lianas D. Daniel Sokol 1

Part I The Competition Law Process

1 The Limits of Antitrust and the Chicago School Tradition George L. Priest 15

2 Competition Law and Human Rights: Striking a Balance Between Business Freedom and Regulatory Intervention Arianna Andreangeli 22

Part II The Economic Limits of Competition Law

3 Limits of Imports from Economics into Competition Law Anne-Lise Sibony 39

4 Complications in the Antitrust Response to Monopsony Jeffrey L. Harrison 54

5 Antitrust and the Close Look: Transaction Cost Economics in Competition Policy Herbert Hovenkamp 66

Part III Competition Law and Its Synergies with Other Areas of Law

6 Anticompetitive Government Regulation D. Daniel Sokol 83

7 A Global Perspective on State Action Damien M. B. Gerard 99

8 IP's Advantages over Antitrust Daniel A. Crane 117

9 Competition Law and Consumer Protection Against Unfair Commercial Practices: A More-than-Complementary Relationship? Paolisa Nebbia 127

Part IV Competition Law and Institutional Design

10 Judicial Scrutiny and Competition Authorities: The Institutional Limits of Antitrust Javier Tapia Santiago Montt 141

11 Competition Authorities: Independence and Advocacy Frédéric Jenny 158

12 Competition Law Remedies: In Search of a Theory Ioannis Lianos 177

Part V Competition Law and Culture

13 How Culture May Change Assumptions in Antitrust Policy Thomas K. Cheng 205

14 Promoting Convergence of Competition Policies in Northeast Asia: Culture-Competition Correlation and Its Implications Ki Jong Lee 221

15 The Limits of Competition Law in Latin America Julián Peña 236

Notes 253

Index 283

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews