BN.com Gift Guide

The Persistence of Poverty: Why the Economics of the Well-Off Can't Help the Poor

Paperback (Print)
Buy Used
Buy Used from BN.com
$13.65
(Save 31%)
Item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging.
Condition: Used – Good details
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $5.41
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 72%)
Other sellers (Paperback)
  • All (10) from $5.41   
  • New (5) from $18.05   
  • Used (5) from $5.41   

Overview

In this important book, one of our boldest and most original thinkers charges that conventional explanations of poverty are mistaken, and that the anti-poverty policies built upon them are doomed to fail. Using science, history, fables, philosophical analysis, and common observation, Charles Karelis engages us and takes us to a deeper grasp of the link between consumption and satisfaction—and from there to a new and persuasive explanation of what keeps poor people poor. Above all, he shows how this fresh perspective can reinspire the long-stalled campaign against poverty.

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Publishers Weekly

This slim volume presents a radical analysis of poverty that turns conventional understandings of the subject upside down. Karelis, a philosophy professor at George Washington University and former president of Colgate, begins with a brief overview of the received wisdom on and conventional arguments regarding poverty, which he argues have been shaped in large part by middle- and upper-class sensibilities of thrift, discipline and long-term thinking; as a result, public policy initiatives have proven largely ineffective. With rigor and passion, Karelis offers a radical reconsideration of the problem, resting on twin premises: the importance of distinguishing between enjoyment and relief (e.g., eating ice cream vs. taking aspirin for a headache), and acknowledging that these motivators/rewards have a different effect on the poor than they do the well-off. Karelis argues that while the middle and upper classes seek an even distribution of "pleasers" to increase "positive satisfaction" over the long run, those acting from a position of insufficiency work for "relievers... goods that reduce pain, unhappiness, or misery" in the moment. As such, what is rational or efficient behavior for the poor is not so for the well-off, and vice versa. Though rich with insight on a subject with broad appeal, Karelis's treatise is not an easy read, particularly for those unfamiliar with economic theory; readers unafraid of technical forays into the Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility and the Epicurean Fallacy will find this important work quite rewarding. (July)

Copyright 2007 Reed Business Information
Gordon C. Winston
“I am very enthusiastic about Charles Karelis's book. It is powerful and important. After a number of years as a senior official dealing with social policy in Washington, this thoughtful philosopher argues impressively for a fundamental shift in perspective in economics. He then goes on to trace the consequences for dealing with poverty clearly. The work merits serious attention from economists, who may well resist at first, but who I suspect will in time be persuaded and excited.”—Gordon C. Winston, Orrin Sage Professor of Political Economy, Williams College
Alan Ryan
“This book is astonishingly lively. It ranges from the facts of life among the American underclass to deep philosophical puzzles about what does and does not count as 'rational' behavior, and will make economists, philosophers, and ordinary engaged citizens rethink just about everything they took for granted about the causes and cures of poverty.”—Alan Ryan, Professor of Politics, Oxford University
Anthony Kronman
"The Persistence of Poverty is an original and enlightening book with a startling thesis. Written with verve and inviting clarity, it will be of interest to philosophers, economists, and public policy planners alike. Its theoretical arguments and practical proposals are sure to be the subject of debate for years to come."—Anthony Kronman, Sterling Professor of Law, Yale Law School
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780300151367
  • Publisher: Yale University Press
  • Publication date: 7/21/2009
  • Edition description: New Edition
  • Pages: 208
  • Product dimensions: 5.40 (w) x 8.10 (h) x 0.60 (d)

Meet the Author

Charles Karelis is Research Professor of Philosophy at The George Washington University. Formerly professor of philosophy at Williams College, director of the Fund for the Improvement of Postsecondary Education, and president of Colgate University, he lives in Washington, D.C.

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

The Persistence of Poverty

Why the Economics of the Well-off Can't Help the Poor
By Charles Karelis

Yale University Press

Copyright © 2007 Charles Karelis
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-300-12090-5


Chapter One

What Poverty Is

Nobody with a practical interest in poverty can be overjoyed to spend time defining it. Semantic issues look like a distraction from the serious business of helping the poor. But those who seek the causes and cures of poverty can easily find themselves in spurious disagreement (or spurious agreement) if they do not first make clear what it is they are talking about.

Two Ways to Define Poverty

Frustratingly, there is a hard choice to be made before one can begin defining poverty. Should the definition be descriptive or stipulative? One approach seems to risk vagueness and ambiguity, while the other seems to risk irrelevance. For in ordinary usage "poverty" has a fuzzy boundary, like the line between red and orange. Who can say at what consumption level being poor ends and being nonpoor begins, even within a given country? What is more, "poverty" appears to mean different things in different parts of the world. Poverty in the United States includes conditions that would not count as poverty in Central Europe, and poverty in Central Europe includes conditions that would not count as poverty in sub-Saharan Africa. This makes it tempting to stipulate adefinition. Why not just pick one of the meanings of this spongy word and tell the reader that for the sake of reaching definite conclusions I will use the word "poverty" to mean such-and-such a level of consumption?

But if stipulating avoids vagueness and ambiguity, it risks irrelevance. For by bringing in a special meaning for the key term "poverty," one takes a chance that one may be answering questions that nobody-at least nobody outside the research and policy community-is asking when they ask about poverty.

In this book I am going to take my chances with the first horn of the dilemma in order to make sure I avoid irrelevance. I propose to define "poverty" in the ordinary sense of the word rather than stipulate a new sense. This seems better for two reasons. First, "poverty" in the ordinary sense is (as we will see) neither as vague nor as ambiguous as it appears. Second, the whole investigation is likelier to be of general interest.

The Ordinary Meaning of "Poverty"

The Oxford English Dictionary defines "poverty" as "indigence," and it defines "indigent" as "lacking in what is requisite." Greg J. Duncan concurs: "Poverty has been defined as a state in which resources are insufficient to meet basic needs." The two definitions are close, but Duncan's amendments are significant. First, the unmet needs constituting poverty are needs for "resources," presumably money or the things it can buy. Second, the unmet needs that make someone poor are "basic" needs-requirements one cannot fail to have, regardless of one's particular purposes.

But this just pushes the definition problem back a step. Now we need to ask which needs are basic. Seeing that we are all physical creatures, basic needs must include physical needs like the need for food. But the needs that matter in deciding whether someone is poor must also include any nonphysical needs that are universal. For example, the needs for dignity, self-respect, and social inclusion are widely seen as universal, even though not directly tied to physiology. Poverty, then, is essentially a lack of physical resources, but it is not necessarily a matter of unmet physical needs. Rather, poverty is having insufficient material resources to meet all basic needs, whether these basic needs stem from our animal nature or not.

Some Things Poverty Is Not: Having Unfulfilled Wants, Having Very Little, and Having Less Than Others

If being poor is not having what one needs, it is not just a matter of not having what one wants. This makes sense because not having everything one wants is a nearly universal condition, after all, while poverty is not. Another implication is that poverty is not a matter of having very little money-or having very little of what money can buy. True, many poor people do have very little, and many people who have very little are poor. But the two things are distinct. If a population's needs are few, they may be able to meet their needs and not be poor, despite a lack of material things. On most of the islands of the Chuuk state, in Micronesia, there are no cars, telephones, clinics, or running water and no regular supply of electricity for domestic use. But the inhabitants are not poor, and this is confirmed by the fact that the English speakers among them do not describe themselves this way. They are not poor because they do not lack what their society recognizes as the requisites of life. It is true that many of the young people of Chuuk envy the living standards of the industrial nations. But they recognize the difference between wanting and needing. Conversely, a natural disaster that somehow annihilated a quarter of the wealth of the United States would leave it with a great deal of wealth, but given the habits of the people it would doubtless be seen as having impoverished the nation.

Another implication of the definition is that being poor is not strictly a matter of having less than others. Studies show that poverty and having less than others are highly correlated, in fact, because people generally feel a need to participate in their society, and this is a need that cannot be easily satisfied at resource levels far below the median. But the idea of poverty is nevertheless distinct from that of having less than others. For one thing, in a nation suffering from famine, even people with more than others-not less-may nevertheless be starving and desperately poor. Conversely, someone might have less than others and not be poor. For grant that there is a universal need for social inclusion, and grant that having much less than others gets in the way of this. Still, relative resource levels could in principle be decoupled from dignity, self-respect, social inclusion, and any other of the nonphysical needs that supposedly have to be fulfilled to avoid poverty. Mickey Kaus recommends that Americans should accord the status of full and respected participant in society to everyone, regardless of their income. If this were to happen, then having less than others would not in fact spell exclusion or therefore poverty, if in fact one's other basic needs were met.

Poverty and Misery

The essence of poverty is lacking the material resources to meet basic needs. But if so, then poverty is bound to be a source of unhappiness. Indeed, that is putting it mildly. Having less than one needs means being threatened with diminishment or even extinction. Does that entail that poor people are unhappy on balance? Common observation shows that being miserable with respect to one's consumption does usually mean being miserable on balance. Having more material goods than one needs may not guarantee happiness, but having less largely guarantees unhappiness.

Against the idea that poverty means misery it might be argued that some of the best things in life are free, and if social inclusion could be detached from income, à Kaus, more of the best things in life could be made free. Maybe poor people could be happy on balance after all. But in the world as we find it, satisfactions that come from nonmaterial goods rarely do more than mitigate the misery of material shortages. Can even the greatest philosophy make an ill-fed, ill-clothed, and ill-housed person happy overall? One person who thought the misery of material deficits could be outweighed by the consolations of philosophy was Plato. He has Socrates insist in The Republic that the wise man in prison is happier than the unwise man outside it, but philosophy would be a much more popular pursuit than it is if Plato had been correct. More cynically, Karl Marx said that religion was the opiate of the masses, meaning the materially poor. But it would be truer to say that religion has sometimes been the weak analgesic of the masses. For opiates kill pain and produce pleasure, while religion mainly consoles. In short, the dictionary definition of poverty, together with the weakness of nonphysical compensations, implies that to be poor is usually to be miserable, period. This is an important result because being miserable on balance imposes a much stronger obligation on others to help than being miserable in this or that particular respect.

Now, not everyone agrees that poor people are typically miserable. One dissenter is Charles Murray, who presents a set of thought experiments designed to show that a Westerner could assimilate into a near-subsistence peasant society, becoming typical in many ways, and yet be quite happy. For instance, he imagines himself becoming a happy rice farmer in Thailand, with a Thai peasant wife, and so on. But Murray's thought experiments do not support his conclusion. He does not succeed in showing that someone can be (a) poor, (b) typical, and (c) happy, because he has not imagined himself poor in the first place. He has imagined himself as having a small income, which is another matter. As we have shown, it is having unmet resource needs, not having few resources, that constitutes poverty. While a typical person can doubtless be happy with few material resources in some societies, that is irrelevant to the question whether a typical person can be happy though poor. Given the meaning of the word "poverty," that is impossible.

Varying Conceptions of Basic Need

So far, so good. But before one can say that the concept of poverty has been made clear enough, there is another issue to be tackled. What gets called a basic need depends on who is making the call. There are many kinds of variation to consider. Individuals living in the same time and place often consider different needs basic. What are typically judged to be requisites in a given society at one time have often been seen as frills at an earlier, less prosperous time in the same society. What are typically judged to be basic needs in one society at a given time may be typically seen as frills in another, contemporary society. And so on. The question is, Is poverty itself something different, depending on these different conceptions of basic needs?

Within a Given Society Varying Conceptions of Basic Need Have Little Impact on What Counts as Poverty

The case of varying views of need in the same society is the simplest. There does seem to be a bit of variation within a given society in what counts as being poor, depending on variations in the level of consumption where people begin to feel the pinch. It makes some sense to say that Smith is poor at a certain level of resources, though his neighbor Jones would not be poor at that same level of resources, if Smith and Jones have different needs. But the concept of poverty is such that any variation in the poverty thresholds between individuals in the same society is bound to be small, even if the variation in their pain thresholds is great. That is because, as others have noted, judgments of poverty put a lot of weight on what are typically seen as basic needs within the society. For instance, a spoiled millionaire in modern America who has developed extraordinary needs for material goods, and who is miserable for lack of billions, does not count as poor. And a monk who happens to be contented with his standard of living is poor nonetheless. Since the millionaire has more than enough to meet what would typically be seen as basic needs in modern America, he is not poor, regardless of the fact that his own needs are unmet, and he is miserable. (Behind this semantic fact there may lie the moral judgment that such a person does not deserve the sympathy implied by the label "poor." For could he not have made himself less vulnerable to frustration by staying in the cultural mainstream and not letting himself develop these needs in the first place?) And conversely for the monk: he counts as poor because a typical person in his position would consider his needs unmet, whether the monk does or not.

In theory, then, it should be possible to draw a line below which people count as poor in a given society, even granting that the point at which individuals feel the pinch of material shortages will vary. The poverty line for a particular society will be that level of consumption below which needs that are typically considered basic in that society are unmet.

An Absolute Standard of Basic Need Across Eras and Nations?

But given that there is in each society a poverty line that transcends differences in individuals' conceptions of basic need, is there also a poverty line that transcends the differences between nations and eras? As Bradley Schiller points out, in the United States in 1936 the ordinary understanding of basic needs implied that about one-third of America was poor, as President Franklin Roosevelt declared at the time, but by the more generous understanding of basic needs that prevails in America today, more than half of that 1936 population was poor. Analogously, just about no one in modern Chuuk has material goods sufficient to meet what are typically seen as basic needs in modern America, but the majority does not see itself as poor, because the Chuukese culture has a lower standard than ours for meeting basic needs. The question raised is, must we always understand "poverty" as an abbreviation for "poverty by the standards of time x in place y"? or is there a way to look beyond the variations and speak of "true poverty"?

It is tempting to absolutize our own intuitions about what constitutes a basic need and simply declare the standards of the past too low and the standards of the future too high. On this way of thinking, some supposedly nonpoor people in 1936-having median incomes but lacking indoor plumbing and electricity-were actually poor, but they did not know it. An especially welcome corollary of this approach is that the just-below-the-future-poverty-line denizens of a future, super-prosperous America-with their reliable cars, their swimming pools, and their three-week vacations-turn out to be not really poor. This corollary is welcome because it is, in simple fact, hard to care about these future people's situation. (One person's frank comment was that the most he would be willing to do to help them would be to send them a message in a time capsule telling them that they are not so badly off.) We probably feel more comfortable rationalizing our indifference to them by saying that they will not really be poor than we do rationalizing our indifference by saying that they will poor, but we do not care. Yet tempting as it may be to absolutize our own intuitions about basic need, it is indefensible because what, after all, is special about our intuitions, as opposed to those of people in the past or the future? Certainly we cannot claim that our intuitions are more typical. In fact, it makes little sense to appeal to what the world's nations and eras have typically considered basic needs, for these conceptions are too diverse.

In the end, there seems to be no way to get around saying that "poverty" is always short for "poverty in place x and time y," and what it means is "having insufficient resources to meet what are typically seen as basic needs in that place and time." This is the best we can do in defining poverty, even if it leaves us in the uncomfortable position of having to say that we do not care much about some of the poverty that exists in richer times and places than our own. Note that to accept this definition is not to grant that "poverty" is ambiguous. Compare the word "edible." "Edible" is not ambiguous just because what horses can digest is different from what humans can digest. What "edible" is is elliptical: the claim that something is edible is always short for "edible by such-and-such a species," but it means the same thing in each context. Likewise, poverty judgments are not ambiguous but elliptical, and once they are fleshed out the meaning is perfectly singular.

Given This Definition of Poverty, Where Is the Poverty Line in the United States Today?

What is the level of resources below which people are unable to meet what are typically seen as basic needs in modern America? and is there a practical earmark for identifying this level as it changes? Obviously no level of consumption can count as adequate if it fails to meet the physiological needs of the human animal for such things as food, clothing, and shelter, and what that level is has been carefully studied. The U.S. government's official answer is the federal poverty threshold. In 2005, that threshold was $10,160 for a single person under age sixty-five, $13,145 for a two-person household under age sixty-five-less than twice the amount for a single person owing to economies of scale-$19,971 for a family of four, and so forth. The debatable aspects of this official poverty threshold have been exhaustively treated in several standard works on poverty and will not be pursued here. They include the question whether it is still valid to assume, as the original drawers of the poverty threshold assumed, that overall physical needs can be met with an income of just three times what is needed for food, given that food accounts for a smaller fraction of the typical budget than it did when the official threshold was defined. A second issue is whether the use of the family as the unit of analysis is appropriate at a time when cohabiting couples and other nontraditional groupings are becoming more prevalent. For instance, it is arguably a weakness of the official poverty standard that it treats a cohabiting couple with $20,000 in total income as made up of poor individuals, while it treats a married couple with $12,600 as nonpoor. However, the technical problems of saying exactly what income suffices for meeting basic physiological needs will not concern us here. They are moot.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from The Persistence of Poverty by Charles Karelis Copyright © 2007 by Charles Karelis. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Preface ix

Acknowledgments xv

1 What Poverty Is 1

2 Behavioral Factors in Poverty 12

3 Some Theories 27

4 A Closer Look at the Inefficiency Argument 49

Appendix. Using Indifference Curves to Identify Utility-Maximizing Allocations 58

5 A New Way to Rationalize the Conduct that Prolongs and Worsens Poverty 61

Appendix. Further Exploration Through Graphical Analysis 92

6 Responses to Challenges and Questions 102

Appendix. The Case of Alfred Marshall 130

7 Policy: What Should We Do Differently If We Believe That Marginal Utility Is Increasing Amid Scarcity? 132

8 Economic Justice Reconsidered 153

Notes 165

Index 183

Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)