The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle to Suarez

Available through our Marketplace sellers.
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (1) from $226.54   
  • Used (1) from $226.54   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$226.54
Seller since 2014

Feedback rating:

(7)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

Very Good
2015 Hardback NEAR FINE 9789004085169 Hardback, xiii, 295 pp. This listing is a new book, a title currently in-print which we order directly and immediately from the publisher. ... Print on Demand title, produced to the highest standard, and there would be a delay in dispatch of around 15 working days. *****PLEASE NOTE: This item is shipping from an authorized seller in Europe. In the event that a return is necessary, you will be able to return your item within the US. To learn more about our European sellers and policies see the BookQuest FAQ section***** Read more Show Less

Ships from: Stroud, Glos, United Kingdom

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Close
Sort by
Sending request ...

Product Details

Table of Contents

Preface XI

I. ARISTOTLE Interpretive Controversy concerning De interp. 9 1
Preliminary Note on Aristotle's Modal Terms 5
Structure of Chapter Nine 6

I. Introduction 8

II. Development of Fatalistic Difficulties 29
Threat of Fatalism 29
Absurdity of Fatalism 42

III. Resolution of Fatalistic Difficulties 47
Necessity and Conditional Necessity 48
Predicating Necessity Collectively and Distri- butively 52
Application to Future Contingent Singular Proposi- tions 55
Summary 57

II AUGUSTINE 59
Turn to Theological Fatalism 59
Augustine's Context of Theodicy 60
Augustine's Problem of Theological Fatalism 63
Augustine's Solution 66
Summary 73
Foreknowledge and Eternity 73

III. BOETHIUS 79
Problem of Theological Fatalism 79
Boethius's Solution 89
Summary 97

IV. THOMAS AQUINAS 99
God's Knowledge of Non-Existents 99
God's Knowledge of Future Contingents 103
Objections to God's Foreknowledge 103
Thomas's Position on God's Foreknowledge 104
Answers to Objections 108
Summary 115
Thomas's Implied Theory of Time 116
God's Knowledge of All Things Through His Essence 118
God's Knowledge as the Cause of Things 121

V.JOHN DUNS SCOTUS 127
Scotus's Position on God's Knowledge 127
Rejection of Previous Opinions 127
Scotus's Own View 134
Objections and Replies 140
Concerning God's Determinate Knowledge 140
Concerning God's Certain and Infallible Knowledge 141
Concerning the Necessity of God's Knowledge 142
Concerning the Compatibility of God's Knowledge with
Contingency 143
Summary 144

VI.WILLIAM OCKHAM 146
God's Determinate Knowledge of Future Contingents 146
Objections 146
Ockham's Position on the Truth Value of Future Con- tingent Propositions 147
Replies to Objections 152
God's Certain and Infallible Knowledge of Future Contin- gents 163
Objections 163
Replies 163
God's Necessary Knowledge of Future Contingents 165
Arguments for Necessity 165
Refutation of Arguments 166
Summary 168

VII.LUIS MOLINA 169
Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents 170
Infallible Knowledge of Future Contingents 171
Reconciliation of Foreknowledge and Contingency 184
Prescience, Providence, and Predestination 198
Prescience 199
Providence 200
Predestination 203
Summary 206

VIII.FRANCISCO SUAREZ 207
God's Knowledge of Actually Future Contingents 208
Basis of God's Foreknowledge of Future Contingents 208
Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge and Future
Contingency 213
Summary 218
God's Knowledge of Conditionally Future Contingents 218
Defense of Divine Middle Knowledge 219
Basis of God's Middle Knowledge 229
Summary 232

Notes 234
Bibliography 281
Index 292

Read More Show Less

First Chapter

PREFACE

The ancient problem of fatalism has resurfaced with surprising vigor in the second half of the twentieth century, especially in its theological form. Already in the first decade of this century, the dean of Polish logicians Jan Lukasiewicz had been moved by the threat of fatalism to draft a multi-valent logic, which he interpreted in terms of three truth values, assigning the third value to future contingent propositions. The theological application of Lukasiewicz's views was made in 1953 and again in 1962 by the Oxford tense logician A. N. Prior, who argued that an omniscient being need not know future contingents. Similar views had been expressed by Charles Hartshorne. G. E. M. Anscombe's reinter- pretation of Aristotle's De interpretation 9 renewed interest in the problem of fatalism and sparked an interpretive controversy over the famous sea battle chapter. In a number of essays in the late fifties and early sixties, Richard Taylor found himself moving ever closer to embracing fatalism, which he definitively did in 1962. Three years later Nelson Pike borrowed Taylor's insights in defending an argument for theological fatalism, thus generating a debate within the pages of the Philosophical Review which continues down to this day. Suddenly literature on this subject appeared everywhere in the journals: Taylor and his defender Steven Cahn battled their many critics; philosophers of religion of various theological stripes both sprang to Pike's defense and issued refutations of it.

About the same time in several other areas of philosophical inquiry, fatalistic motifs were also cropping up, for the most part independently of the debates surrounding Taylor and Pike. In 1954 and again ten years later, Michael Dummett argued that the logical objection to backward causation is parallel to the argument for fatalism, only the tenses being different, so that rejection of fatalism entails the logical possibility of backward causation, and an extensive debate over the logical possibility and problems of retrocausation ensued. Proponents of time travel similarly charged that their detractors were committing the same logical fallacies as the proponents of fatalism. Meanwhile, as the experimental evidence for the parapsychological phenomenon of precognition grew, philosophers disputed whether precognition and future contingency are compatible, thus closely paralleling the debate going on among the philosophers of religion. In 1969 Robert Nozick passed on to the philosophical public a puzzle known as Newcomb's Paradox, and in the devisive discussion which followed, many saw this puzzle as a paradigm illustration of the problem of theological fatalism.

The contemporary debate has been accompanied by a revival of interest in the historical treatments of the problem of fatalism and, in particular, theological fatalism. The interpretive controversy over the so-
called standard and non-standard interpretation of Aristotle has already been mentioned. Prior and Pike in their articles appealed to discussions of the problem by Augustine, Boetiiius, Aquinas, and Ockham. William Rowe opened a dispute on the proper understanding of Augustine with regard to divine foreknowledge and human freedom. Anthony Kenny re- examined Aquinas's contribution to the subject. Especially great was the interest stirred in Ockham's views by the translation of several of his works, particularly his Tractatus on divine foreknowledge and human freedom, translated by Adams and Kretzmann. Most recently Alvin Plantinga's rediscovery of Luis Molina's doctrine of middle knowledge has fanned the fires of that old controversy, and Freddoso's forthcoming translation of Molina's Concordia will undoubtedly be met with great interest. So rich are these earlier discussions that Kenny opines, "Nine- teenth and twentieth century treatments of these matters have added very little to the work of earlier philosophers and theologians."*

Unfortunately, despite the renewed interest, these earlier works remain largely misunderstood. The names of many historical figures are bandied about as labels for positions which are not recognizably theirs.
In the case of other figures, these writers are simply ignored. Aristotle's views on the subject can only be determined by a careful exegesis of the Greek text. Augustine's views are portrayed in contemporary literature in basically opposed ways. The Boethian concept of eternity, so crucial to his solution to theological fatalism, has been recently miscontrued by its defenders. Philosophers have been quick to criticize Aquinas's views without complete understanding. Duns Scotus's very provocative contribution to the debate, including his rejection of Thomas's position, has never been translated and so is little known or understood.
Undoubtedly, however, it is Ockham's views which have been the subject of the most distortion in contemporary debates, and what passes for "Ockhamism" in many quarters today is a gross caricature of what he held. Molina's views have been known largely only from secondary literature, since a translation of his Concordia has not been published; his creative and fertile work on this subject merits careful study. Finally,
Suarez's works on divine foreknowledge and middle knowledge have never been translated and are therefore generally unknown; yet his writings on this subject rank second in importance only to Molina's.

Hitherto, there has not yet been a study of monograph length devoted to the historical debate over theological fatalism. There is the article "Future Contingents" by Calvin Normore in Cambridge History of Lato Medieval Philosophy, which, given its length, can only sketch the general lines of each figure's position. Two unpublished dissertations on this subject do exist: J.R. Cassidy's "Logic and Determinism: A History of the Problem of Future Contingent Propositions from Aristotle to Ockham" (1965) and Paul Streveler's "The Problem of Future Contingents from Aristotle through the Fifteenth Century" (1970), but these also tend to sacrifice depth in favor of breath in their surveys of the problem's history. The closest thing to a published monograph on this subject is the recent, fine collection of papers originally presented at a conference at Ohio State University in 1982 and edited by Tamar Rudavsky under the title Divine Omniscience and OmmPotence in Medieval Philosophy.** This collection is especially helpful in bringing to light Islamic and Jewish perspectives on theological fatalism, as only one essay in the volume treats Christian perspectives on this problem, which will be the focus of our attention in the present book.

The present work attempts to present in-depth case studies of the views of eight of the most important thinkers who have dealt with the problem of theological fatalism. It is not intended to be a history of the debate nor to catalogue all the various options proffered as solutions to the problem. Indeed, my primary interest is in seeing how Christian thinkers commit- ted both to divine knowledge of the future and to freedom reconcile those commitments. It is for this reason that the otherwise interesting contribu- tion of a thinker like Gersonides, who denied the validity of the Principle of Bivalence for future contingent propositions and consequently God's knowledge of future contingents, is left aside. Our interest lies with those philosophers or theologians who wanted to adhere both to future contingency and God's knowledge of such events.

The research for this book was conducted principally during two sabbaticals, first as a visiting scholar at the University of Arizona in Tucson in 1982-83 and subsequently at the Bibliothèque Nationale in Paris in 1985. Expressions of acknowledgement to the various individuals who assisted me in the research and writing of this work may be found in the appropriate individual chapters. But I should like to acknowledge here the hard work of my secretary Jo Lewis, who was responsible for the production of the typescript.

Santa Barbara, California WILLIAM LANE CRAIG

*Anthony Kenny, The God of the Philosophers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974), p. 13.
**Tamar Rudavsky, Divine Omniscience and Omnipotence in Medieval Philosophy.. Islamic,
Jewish, and Christian Perspectives, Synthese Historical Library (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
Reidel, 1985).

Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)