Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor

Hardcover (Print)
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $19.96
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 60%)
Other sellers (Hardcover)
  • All (9) from $19.96   
  • New (3) from $44.08   
  • Used (6) from $19.96   
Close
Sort by
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Note: Marketplace items are not eligible for any BN.com coupons and promotions
$44.08
Seller since 2008

Feedback rating:

(17613)

Condition:

New — never opened or used in original packaging.

Like New — packaging may have been opened. A "Like New" item is suitable to give as a gift.

Very Good — may have minor signs of wear on packaging but item works perfectly and has no damage.

Good — item is in good condition but packaging may have signs of shelf wear/aging or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Acceptable — item is in working order but may show signs of wear such as scratches or torn packaging. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Used — An item that has been opened and may show signs of wear. All specific defects should be noted in the Comments section associated with each item.

Refurbished — A used item that has been renewed or updated and verified to be in proper working condition. Not necessarily completed by the original manufacturer.

New
Brand New, Perfect Condition, Please allow 4-14 business days for delivery. 100% Money Back Guarantee, Over 1,000,000 customers served.

Ships from: Westminster, MD

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$44.09
Seller since 2007

Feedback rating:

(23419)

Condition: New
BRAND NEW

Ships from: Avenel, NJ

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
$77.14
Seller since 2011

Feedback rating:

(7)

Condition: New
2008 Hardcover New Book New and in stock. 10/5/2008. *****PLEASE NOTE: This item is shipping from an authorized seller in Europe. In the event that a return is necessary, you ... will be able to return your item within the US. To learn more about our European sellers and policies see the BookQuest FAQ section***** Read more Show Less

Ships from: Morden, United Kingdom

Usually ships in 1-2 business days

  • Canadian
  • International
  • Standard, 48 States
  • Standard (AK, HI)
Page 1 of 1
Showing All
Close
Sort by

Overview

"In Thinking of Others, Ted Cohen argues that the ability to imagine oneself as another person is an indispensable human capacity - as essential to moral awareness as it is to literary appreciation - and that this talent for identification is the same as the talent for metaphor. To be able to see oneself as someone else, whether the someone else is a real person or a fictional character, is to exercise the ability to deal with metaphor and other figurative language. The underlying faculty, Cohen argues, is the same - simply the ability to think of one thing as another when it plainly is not." An original meditation on the necessity of imagination to moral and aesthetic life, Thinking of Others is an important contribution to philosophy and literary theory.
Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

Choice
The important, intriguing subject of this small book by Cohen—one's capacity to understand others—is full of perplexing puzzles. Through careful analysis of interesting examples, Cohen makes readers wonder about some of the major impasses in mutual understanding between people with different religious perspectives, with different racial and social experiences, and even with allegiances to different baseball teams.
— S.A. Mason
NewYorker.com
Ted Cohen's little philosophical essay on how metaphor gets us to think of others, was tremendous.
— James Wood
NewYorker.com
Ted Cohen's little philosophical essay on how metaphor gets us to think of others was tremendous.
— James Wood
Choice
The important, intriguing subject of this small book by Cohen—one's capacity to understand others—is full of perplexing puzzles. Through careful analysis of interesting examples, Cohen makes readers wonder about some of the major impasses in mutual understanding between people with different religious perspectives, with different racial and social experiences, and even with allegiances to different baseball teams.
— S.A. Mason
Philosophy in Review
This is really philosophy at its best: clearly written and free from jargon, sophisticated yet unpretentious, and highly engaging.
— Jeanette Bicknell
Mind
Cohen has given us, in wonderfully readable and analytically acute form, an unforgettable study of a complexly interwoven set of linguistic, perceptual, and imaginative abilities that not only make us who we are, but make us who we are together.
— Garry L. Hagberg
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
[W]hy not invest in Cohen's book? I assure you it will return handsome dividends, even in the present economy.
— Peter Kivy
NewYorker.com - James Wood
Ted Cohen's little philosophical essay on how metaphor gets us to think of others was tremendous.
Philosophy in Review - Jeanette Bicknell
This is really philosophy at its best: clearly written and free from jargon, sophisticated yet unpretentious, and highly engaging.
Mind - Garry L. Hagberg
Cohen has given us, in wonderfully readable and analytically acute form, an unforgettable study of a complexly interwoven set of linguistic, perceptual, and imaginative abilities that not only make us who we are, but make us who we are together.
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism - Peter Kivy
[W]hy not invest in Cohen's book? I assure you it will return handsome dividends, even in the present economy.
Choice - S.A. Mason
The important, intriguing subject of this small book by Cohen—one's capacity to understand others—is full of perplexing puzzles. Through careful analysis of interesting examples, Cohen makes readers wonder about some of the major impasses in mutual understanding between people with different religious perspectives, with different racial and social experiences, and even with allegiances to different baseball teams.
From the Publisher

"Ted Cohen's little philosophical essay on how metaphor gets us to think of others was tremendous."--James Wood, NewYorker.com

"This is really philosophy at its best: clearly written and free from jargon, sophisticated yet unpretentious, and highly engaging."--Jeanette Bicknell, Philosophy in Review

"Cohen has given us, in wonderfully readable and analytically acute form, an unforgettable study of a complexly interwoven set of linguistic, perceptual, and imaginative abilities that not only make us who we are, but make us who we are together."--Garry L. Hagberg, Mind

"Ted Cohen's work on metaphor is well known in the profession, so it comes as no surprise to us that he has now written a splendid book on the subject."--Peter Kivy, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

"The important, intriguing subject of this small book by Cohen--one's capacity to understand others--is full of perplexing puzzles. Through careful analysis of interesting examples, Cohen makes readers wonder about some of the major impasses in mutual understanding between people with different religious perspectives, with different racial and social experiences, and even with allegiances to different baseball teams."--S.A. Mason, Choice

"[W]hy not invest in Cohen's book? I assure you it will return handsome dividends, even in the present economy."--Peter Kivy, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780691137469
  • Publisher: Princeton University Press
  • Publication date: 9/15/2008
  • Series: Princeton Monographs in Philosophy Series
  • Edition description: New Edition
  • Pages: 104
  • Product dimensions: 5.80 (w) x 8.50 (h) x 0.60 (d)

Meet the Author


Ted Cohen is a professor of philosophy at the University of Chicago and the author of "Jokes: Philosophical Thoughts on Joking Matters."
Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

THINKING OF OTHERS

ON THE TALENT FOR METAPHOR
By Ted Cohen

PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 2008 Princeton University Press
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-13746-9


Chapter One

The Talent for Metaphor

Nonetheless, I agree that there is a pictorial dimension to metaphor and that the perspective it generates cannot be expressed propositionally. -Josef Stern

We may, therefore, regard the metaphorical sentence as a "Duck-Rabbit"; it is a sentence that may simultaneously be regarded as presenting two different situations; looked at one way, it describes the actual situation, and looked at the other way, an hypothetical situation with which that situation is being compared. -Roger White

There is mystery at the heart of metaphor. During the past several years a number of capable authors have done much to clarify the topic, and they have shown that some earlier central theses about the nature of metaphor are untenable. What they have shown, in particular, is that the import of a significant metaphor cannot be delivered literally, that is, in general, that a metaphorical statement has no literal statement that is its equivalent.

It may or may not be prudent to regard the import of a metaphor as a meaning. If it is, then a metaphorical sentence has two meanings, one literal and one metaphorical. If not, then there is only one meaning, the literal meaning, and the metaphorical import has to be understood in another way. But in either case there will be a metaphorical import that a competent audience will grasp. How the audience does this is, in the end, a mystery.

In the case of a metaphor of the form 'A is B', some comparison is indicated of the properties of A with the properties of B. An early idea, persistent at least since Aristotle, is that this comparison can be made explicit in a formulation of the form 'A is like B' and this leads to the further idea that the import of the metaphor can be expressed as an explicit, literal comparison of A with B.

Both ideas are mistaken, the second more seriously misleading than the first. The first idea, on its face, is simply and wildly implausible. In general, and certainly in the case of literal statements, 'A is B' and 'A is like B' are not equivalent. For instance, 'Aristotle is like Plato' is true: they are both Greek, both Athenians, both philosophers, both long dead, &c, while 'Aristotle is Plato' is false. There is no compelling reason to think that this obvious nonequivalence disappears when 'A is B' happens to be a metaphor, unless, of course, it were the case that a metaphor 'A is B' is somehow, perhaps by convention, to be understood as an alternative formulation of the literal simile 'A is like B', and there seems no good reason to suppose this to be the case.

The second idea is that the 'A is like B' associated with the metaphor 'A is B' is not itself metaphorical but is literal, and as seductive as this idea has been, it is mistaken. The mistake can be exposed using the useful if timeworn example 'Juliet is the sun'. If the import of Romeo's declaration were a literal comparison expressed in 'Juliet is like the sun', then the relevant comparison would be of properties literally possessed by both Juliet and the sun. There is no shortage of such properties: both Juliet and the sun occupy space, have mass, are visible, &c. But these properties are irrelevant to what Romeo hopes to communicate. What matters are these other shared properties: both Juliet and the sun are warming, they both illuminate Romeo's world, &c. And these properties-the significant ones-are indeed literal properties of the sun, but they are metaphorical properties of Juliet.

So even if a metaphor were "reducible" to a simile or similes (already a dubious reduction), many of the most important similes themselves would also be figurative, not literal. Of course there often are literal similarities, especially in the cases I am most interested in, those in which I imagine myself to be another person. When I imagine myself to be King David, for instance, it is obviously relevant that both he and I are men, both heterosexually active, both tempted to injure others in pursuit of our own desires, and so on.

It seems obviously true that a metaphor 'A is B' induces one to think of A as B, and this leads to new thoughts about A. How this happens is a wonderful mystery, and the ability to do it, to "see" A as B, is an indispensable human ability I am calling the talent for metaphor. This is a talent not just for making a metaphor or grasping one, not if one thinks of that only in terms of producing or understanding a single sentence. The talent is not restricted in this way: in fact it is a talent for seizing metaphors and then enlarging and altering them.

Here is a relatively elaborate metaphor from Richard Stern:

There are, I think, three very different sorts of literary experience: the writer's the reader's, and the critic's, the last two being as distinct as the first from them.... If we analogize the writer to an assassin, the reader is the corpse, the critic the coroner-detective.

This figure is a perfect illustration of two features common to metaphorical language although not always so strikingly present. First is a metaphor's capacity to suggest other, related metaphors, almost by implication. Thus if you think of a critic as someone explaining the effect of a book upon a reader, and you then think of a coroner as someone who paradigmatically explains effects, you think of the critic as a coroner, and this leads to seeing the reader as a victim and the author as his victimizer, and, although Stern does not bother to note this, it leads to thinking of the book itself as a weapon. Given this much, a competent metaphor appreciator is led to much, much more. Perhaps Tolstoy kills with large, overpowering weapons, while Proust sedates you to death. What about Hemingway? Does he use a machine gun? A sniper rifle? And then, undoubtedly, you will recall the virtually idiomatic response to a joker, "You slay me." And on and on.

But second, you may resist the metaphor or some part of it. It is extraordinary and very striking that Stern thinks of a writer as a killer. If you don't see writers in that way, but are still struck by the irresistible aptness of Stern's designation of the critic as someone like a pathologist, someone seeking to understand the effect upon a reader of what he reads, then what will you do to amend Stern's figures? Perhaps you think of a novelist as a therapist, improving the muscle tone or endurance of his reader, and then the critic becomes perhaps the judge in a bodybuilding contest, or, better, a doctor who appraises your health after you submitted to the therapist he recommended, and can explain just why the therapy had this effect.

Both ways of thinking of writing metaphorically, of course, lead to the endlessly beguiling question of why the reader submits to the author's ministrations. In Stern's figure, we must ask, why does one expose oneself to an assassin? I don't know Stern's answer, but I think it must be wonderful to contemplate. In the substitute figure, the question of why one goes to a therapist is less interesting, less potent, but still instructive.

Calling a writer an assassin is perhaps an uncomplimentary reference to the writer, although I doubt Stern thinks of his metaphor in this way. Many metaphors are intended, precisely, to be devices for saying negative things about their subjects.

Suppose you wish to say something uncomplimentary about Bart, and you mean to do it using a metaphor. You will say that Bart is an X, and the result will be an unpleasant depiction of Bart. You have to choose some noun to put in place of 'X', and there are, surprisingly, two classes of candidates. In the more obvious choice, you will pick the name of something inherently disagreeable, say the word 'maggot'. This gives 'Bart is a maggot', a mean thing, indeed, to say when speaking of Bart. On the other hand, there is nothing intrinsically unpleasant or disagreeable about dogs, and yet if you choose 'dog' for 'X', you will get 'Bart is a dog', which might well be an insult to Bart.

An historical example of a choice of the second kind, of something not in itself negative, is Churchill's remark about Mussolini, 'Mussolini is a utensil'. There is nothing whatever negative in calling a fork or a knife or a screwdriver a utensil, but something happens when Mussolini is seen as a utensil.

There are two lessons to be learned from these examples, the first interesting but less problematic than the second. The first lesson is that whether or not metaphors have new meanings, and whether or not the principal use of a metaphor is to communicate the speaker's feeling about his subject, it remains true that different choices of predicates give different imports. Churchill might have called Mussolini a wolf or the devil or a parasite, but none of those has the same import as calling him a utensil. That is, whether or not this is strictly a matter of semantics, there are relatively specific imports or depictions of ideas presented in metaphors, including those meant to insult or degrade. To think of Mussolini as a swine is to be uncomplimentary to Mussolini, no doubt, but to think of him as a utensil is, among other things, to think of him in his relation to Hitler, which is significantly more specific, and, one might say, even more accurate and informative.

The second lesson is that the mystery of metaphor-the mystery of one thing's being seen or thought of as another-is even more enigmatic than one might have expected. To see Bart as a maggot is to see Bart in a rather poor light, so to speak, but that seems to be because maggots are already in bad repute. But seeing Bart as a dog, or Mussolini as a utensil is different. Something happens when one sees Mussolini as a utensil that also puts Mussolini in a bad light, but not because of any negative association with utensils. It is Mussolini-seen-as-a-utensil that is disagreeable.

When one sees something as an X, one is seeing a new entity, a kind of compound. To see Bart as a maggot is to see something disagreeable, and to see anything as a maggot would be to see something disagreeable. To see Mussolini as a utensil is to see something distasteful, but not because anything seen in that way would be distasteful-for instance, one might see language as a utensil.

The overall lesson, which connects this observation to Arnold Isenberg's idea of "critical communication," is that a leading aim of many metaphor-makers is the communication of some feelings they have about the subjects of their metaphors, and the often hoped-for inducement of similar feelings in those who grasp their metaphors. Both the description, say, of Mussolini, and the attendant feeling are specific. Churchill did not want only to present Mussolini in a bad light, but to present him lit in a very specific way, and he wanted not only for us to feel negatively about Il Duce, but to have the feelings that go with thinking of Mussolini as a utensil. Mussolini might well also have been a swine, but that is different, a different depiction with a different attendant feeling.

Metaphorical sentences come in all forms-imperative, interrogative, and so on-but the only concern here is with those that are declarative sentences, sentences used for making statements, and among those the only interest is in those whose form is 'A is B'. There are still a number of possible logical forms, for, in the first place, the 'is' may be the 'is' of predication or the 'is' of identity, and in the second place, both 'A' and 'B' may be either common nouns, proper nouns, or singular terms. Here are two random examples.

Yale men are poor little lambs. Cole Porter is a poor little lamb.

The kind of metaphor I hope to exploit is the one whose subject term is a proper name or singular term, specifically either the name of a person or a singular pronoun. When the 'is' is of identity, then the form may be 'I am N' where 'N' is a singular term, proper name, or definite description, something referring to a specific person. When the 'is' is of predication, the form will be 'I am a G', where 'G' is a general term.

This bothersome, quasi-technical terminology can be dropped once it is clear that what I am trying to describe is what is at the center of one's thought when one imagines being someone or something other than who or what one is. It is what comes to mind when I ask,

What if I were Robert Pinsky? What if I were a Christian? What if I were a lover of Wagner's music?

What comes to mind, I think, are thoughts expressed in these sentences:

I am Robert Pinsky. I am a Christian. I am a Wagner lover.

and I construe all these sentences to be metaphors. I suppose this is a dubious construal, and many students of metaphor will find these sentences alien to their sense of metaphor. I concede that this is a novel construal, but I ask indulgence because what one must do to grasp any of these sentences is to think of one thing as something it plainly is not, and that, I think, is exactly what one must do to grasp a metaphor. Then even if it is inapt to call these sentences metaphors, the knack for grasping them is the same as the knack for grasping metaphors, and so I will call them metaphors of personal identification, and I will call the ability to grasp them the talent for metaphor.

In a metaphor of personal identification, usually, a person is said to be either another person or a person of a different kind, as in, for instance,

Juliet is the sun. The Lord is my shepherd. The poor are the Negroes of Europe.

I will be concentrating on cases in which the person is oneself, paying most attention to the identification of oneself with another person, cases of the form 'I am N' where 'N' is a singular term referring to a person. It will do to write such a case as

I = N, <

but doing so signals the need for a qualification. The '=' indicating the 'is' of identity, when used in a metaphor, is not exactly the usual relation of identity. Standard identity is a symmetric relation. Thus, X = Y if and only if Y = X. The reason why this is not true of metaphorical identifications is this: to grasp a metaphor is to see one thing as another, and it is not, in general, the same to see X as Y, as it is to see Y as X.

In understanding this it may help to ponder a short story.

A Jewish man named 'Lev', living in eastern Europe in the late nineteenth century, one day says to some friends, "If I were the Czar, I would be richer than the Czar."

"How could that be?" asks his friend. "If you were the Czar, you would have all the Czar's wealth, and so you would be exactly as rich as the Czar. How could you be richer?"

"Well," says Lev, "if I were the Czar, on the side I would give Hebrew lessons."

What's wrong with this? Is anything wrong with it?

Well, for a start, the Czar wouldn't give Hebrew lessons because, in the first place, it's just not something the Czar would do, and, secondly, it's not something the Czar could do, because, of course, the Czar doesn't know the language. But of course Lev knows Hebrew, and in fact right now he does make a little money giving Hebrew lessons.

So, would you say that if the Czar were Lev, he would be even richer? Does that seem different from asking, what if Lev were the Czar?

Do you feel like saying either of these?

If Lev were the Czar, he wouldn't know Hebrew. If the Czar were Lev, he would know Hebrew.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from THINKING OF OTHERS by Ted Cohen Copyright © 2008 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Contents

Acknowledgments....................ix
Chapter One The Talent for Metaphor....................1
Chapter Two Being a Good Sport....................13
Chapter Three From the Bible: Nathan and David....................19
Chapter Four Real Feelings, Unreal People....................29
Chapter Five More from the Bible: Abraham and God....................53
Chapter Six More Lessons from Sports....................57
Chapter Seven Oneself Seen by Others....................65
Chapter Eight Oneself as Oneself....................67
Chapter Nine Lessons from Art....................69
Chapter Ten The Possibility of Conversation, Moral and Otherwise....................79
Chapter Eleven Conclusion: In Praise of Metaphor....................85
Index....................87
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)