BN.com Gift Guide

Words, Thoughts, and Theories / Edition 1

Paperback (Print)
Used and New from Other Sellers
Used and New from Other Sellers
from $9.37
Usually ships in 1-2 business days
(Save 62%)
Other sellers (Paperback)
  • All (7) from $9.37   
  • New (4) from $23.77   
  • Used (3) from $9.37   

Overview

Words, Thoughts, and Theories articulates and defends the "theory theory" of cognitive and semantic development, the idea that infants and young children, like scientists, learn about the world by forming and revising theories, a view of the origins of knowledge and meaning that has broad implications for cognitive science.

Gopnik and Meltzoff interweave philosophical arguments and empirical data from their own and other's research. Both the philosophy and the psychology, the arguments and the data, address the same fundamental epistemological question: How do we come to understand the world around us?

Recently, the theory theory has led to much interesting research. However, this is the first book to look at the theory in extensive detail and to systematically contrast it with other theories. It is also the first to apply the theory to infancy and early childhood, to use the theory to provide a framework for understanding semantic development, and to demonstrate that language acquisition influences theory change in children.The authors show that children just beginning to talk are engaged in profound restructurings of several domains of knowledge.

These restructurings are similar to theory changes in science, and they influence children's early semantic development, since children's cognitive concerns shape and motivate their use of very early words. But, in addition, children pay attention to the language they hear around them and this too reshapes their cognition, and causes them to reorganize their theories.

Theories of childhood learning that reflect a cognitive & scientific base of understanding, language acquisition.

Read More Show Less

What People Are Saying

From the Publisher
"Beyond the good science that they contribute to their ownidea... it is surprising and wonderful how Gopnik and Meltzofftranscend their own field to demonstratethe relevance of theirresearch to other disciplines." Shaun Gallagher , Journal ofConsciousness Studies

"The book is astonishing in its scope and clarity. It successfullyintegrates philosophy, cognitive development, and cognitive science in away that has rarely if ever been done.

The idea that childrendevelop theories which evolve and reorganize into newer and more powerfultheories, like mini-scientists, is of course not new; but in Gopnik andMeltzoff's hands it received a thorough treatment, across such a wide rangeof domains." Simon Baron-Cohen, Lecturer inPsychopathology, Departments ofExperimental Psychology and Psychiatry, University ofCambridge

Shaun Gallagher, Journal of Consciousness Studie
Beyond the good science that they contribute to their own idea... it is surprising and wonderful how Gopnik and Meltzoff transcend their own field to demonstratethe relevance of their research to other disciplines.
Simon Baron-Cohen
The book is astonishing in its scope and clarity. It successfully integrates philosophy, cognitive development, and cognitive science in away that has rarely if ever been done. The idea that childrendevelop theories which evolve and reorganize into newer and more powerful theories, like mini-scientists, is of course not new; but in Gopnik and Meltzoff's hands it received a thorough treatment, across such a wide rangeof domains.
Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780262571265
  • Publisher: MIT Press
  • Publication date: 7/31/1998
  • Series: Learning, Development, and Conceptual Change
  • Edition description: Reprint
  • Edition number: 1
  • Pages: 350
  • Product dimensions: 6.00 (w) x 9.00 (h) x 0.60 (d)

Read an Excerpt

One influential approach to cognitive development began almost eighty years ago in Paris. With a treble "formation" in biology, logic and psychoanalysis, Jean Piaget conducted his first investigations with children. Charged with the task of standardizing a set of reasoning tasks, Piaget was delighted to discover that various concepts were neither innate nor open to explicit teaching, but spontaneously constructed by the child. Piaget's claims have been under sustained scrutiny, especially in the past thirty years, and the clamour of that empirical attack has been sufficient to convince many lay observers that Piagetian theory is dead. Insiders would probably admit, however, that several of his ideas are alive and well, if not universally accepted: that children are constantly engaged in reconstructing the conceptual vessel that they sail in; that, in so doing, they move from a less adequate conception of the world to a more adequate conception; that the main engine of cognitive development is an endogenous, constructive process that cannot be hurried; and that attempts to teach children cannot by-pass that constructive process because children invariably use it to make sense of — or distort — whatever instruction they receive. Despite the continuing power of these ideas, the past thirty years of research on cognitive development have seen various efforts to recast the Piagetian programme. First, Piaget assumed that the infant began life with a set of sensory-motor reactions but no conception of the objects, persons, or space that elicited those reactions. Given the plethora of striking findings with very young infants, few investigators these days would be willing to acceptsuch radical naivete. Second, Piaget was inclined to think of the child as concurrently engaged in various interconnected intellectual projects concerning space, time, weight, and so forth — making progress in each at roughly the same rate. Contemporary research favours instead the notion of "domain-specificity" — the possibility that the child's grasp of, for example, the principles of everyday physics need have little connection with his or her grasp of everyday psychology, so that a given child may be precocious in one and slow in the other. Third, although Piaget was intrigued by analogies between the young child's conception of say speed or time, and similar notions to be found in the history of science, he emphasized analogies of content rather than process. Indeed, he was very far from supposing that the intellectual groping of the pre-schooler has much to do with the research activity of the scientist. Several current theorists, by contrast, press for a much more pervasive analogy at the level of process. According to these investigators, the process of conceptual change in childhood is deeply akin to the process of theory construction, revision and replacement among scientists, notwithstanding differences of method. Alison Gopnik and Andrew Meltzoff acknowledge their debt to Piaget, and also emphasize, to varying degrees, these three revisions: the competence of the young infant, the notion of domain-specificity, and the child as scientist. Their account of cognitive development runs roughly as follows. At birth, the baby is equipped with a set of "dedicated" interpretative devices or modules. Armed with these devices, the toddler constructs a variety of mini-theories, one dedicated to the behaviour of inanimate objects, another to animate agents and so forth. These mini-theories come under increasing strain when the child is faced with observational anomalies. As in the history of science, the anomalies are handled by ad hoc postulates tacked on to the existing theory. As time goes on, the new postulate and its implications are digested more fully to the point where they can displace or trigger a reorganization of existing ideas. Gopnik and Meltzoff apply this vision to children's understanding of three domains: objects and their appearances; human agency; and conceptual kinds or categories. Gopnik and Meltzoff make two further claims about the developing relation between language and thought, both connected to their view of the child as scientist. First, they argue that a theoretical shift in, for example, the way that the child conceives of objects will have an impact on the child's use of language. Thus, as in science, a theoretical shift has repercussions for linguistic practice. Second, exposure to key theoretical terms triggers a conceptual search for their meaning. By implication, the language to which children are exposed offers an endless series of take home exercises that children need to work through. Hence, according to Gopnik and Meltzoff, the traffic between conceptual development and language is bi-directional. It does not flow only from cognition to language, as Piaget typically argued. In setting out their arguments regarding each domain, Gopnik and Meltzoff review the available evidence in a creative fashion. Anyone looking for an overview of much of the most exciting research in the past ten to fifteen years on early conceptual development would do well to start with their book. Their co-ordination of two lines of evidence that are normally kept separate — children's understanding of the permanence and the appearance of objects — is especially intriguing. It allows them to discuss not just how the child conceives of an object in impersonal space but also whether the child understands when and how an object is seen by other observers. This conjunction also implies — contrary to strong versions of the domain-specificity thesis — that the child's grasp of naive physics cannot be neatly separated from his or her grasp of naive psychology. More important for an assessment of the likely impact of their book is an evaluation of their over-arching analogy: the child as scientist. Is the analogy well founded, and will it advance the field? First, we can acknowledge, along with Gopnik and Meltzoff, that one rival theoretical position has major problems by comparison. Some investigators, impressed with the competence of the young infant, have proposed that certain types of core or modular knowledge last a lifetime. For example, it has been argued that infants have a module that enables them to understand the behaviour of medium-sized, three-dimensional solid objects — no constructive process being needed. Similarly, it has been argued that infants have a module dedicated to the understanding of propositional attitudes, such as beliefs and desires. The problem for the modularity thesis is that infants and young children display persistent errors in their dealings with both objects and attitudes, errors that eventually get sorted out. Admittedly, modular approaches have a variety of answers to these early limitations, but the answers typically involve some non-modular process to explain either a gap between competence and performance or a delay in the activation of the relevant module. Given that error correction is abundant in the course of cognitive development, the upshot is that any modular account has to saddle itself with an unsatisfactory mix of modularity and non-modularity or modularity and pre modularity to even make a start at explaining developmental change. By contrast, the child-as-scientist analogy is perfectly content with error correction — indeed, that is one of its major explanatory targets. Gopnik and Meltzoff are also right to insist that the children are not simple empiricists. They do make empirical generalizations, but these generalizations are the product of underlying theoretical commitments about the nature of reality. For example, when infants watch an object move behind a screen, they not only predict its reappearance at the far end of the screen, they also "commit" themselves to the enduring existence o the object while it is invisible. Proof of that commitment is their puzzlement at various types of mysterious disappearance or conjuring trick that imply the non-endurance of the object. Gopnik and Meltzoff argue that empiricist accounts, including the computer-based models of neural networks proposed by connectionists, are unable to account for the characteristic features of theory change: the emergence of such ontological commitments, and their elaboration or replacement in the course of cognitive development. However, this is to underestimate contemporary connectionist models. For example, with respect to object permanence, a couple of recent models have shown how a network that predicts the reappearance of an object from behind a screen with increasing accuracy, also "commits" itself to the enduring existence of that object during its invisibility. Moreover, attempts to model children's understanding of a see-saw or balance beam have successfully reproduced the way that children focus first on weight, and then gradually acknowledge the role of position on the arm. Indeed, Gopnik and Meltzoff ignore the connectionist threat to their own stance. It is important for Gopnik and Meltzoff that there be a clear divide between the predictions that children derive from their theory-based, ontological commitments and the a-theoretical, empirical generalizations which feed into such theories. In connectionist accounts, by contrast, those learning algorithms that can arrive at empirical generalizations — for example, about what sounds are permitted to follow one another in English — are not obviously different from the algorithms that go on to generate first one "commitment" and then another. In short, on connectionist accounts, the child as empiricist, and the child as theorizer, are two facets of the same type of learner. Still, notwithstanding the threat from connectionism, Gopnik and Meltzoff make a provocative case for taking the analogy between child and scientist seriously. Part of their claim is that the analogy is probably better stated the other way round. It is not so much that children are like scientists, but rather that scientists are like children, because — unlike most adults — scientists retain a conceptual stance that is characteristic of childhood: they remain open to contradiction and revision in the face of contradictory evidence. This assertion is part of a larger agenda advocated by Gopnik and Meltzoff, namely that although the traditional vehicle for the study of theoretical change has been the history and philosophy of science, a more natural and ubiquitous vehicle is the study of theoretical change in children. In setting out this agenda, they draw an intriguing analogy. Prior to Darwin, horticulturists had developed some understanding of selective breeding Guided by an understanding of this process of "artificial" selection, Darwin postulated a process of natural selection, IN the wake of Darwinian theory, the study of taxonomy became less preoccupied with the demarcation of a supposedly fixed set of species, and more concerned with questions about the origin and transformation of species. Moreover, the process of artificial selection was gradually seen for what it was: a late-appearing exploitation of a mechanism that had operated blindly and unremittingly throughout evolution. Gopnik and Meltzoff conceive of the same prospect for the study of conceptual change. Science is best seen as a recent upstart — a more or less deliberate exploitation of some cognitive machinery that has been around for about 50,000 years, and is best exemplified by cognitive development in children. On this view, the study of the history of science will gradually be seen as the intellectual equivalent of studying horticulture; the mainstream study of conceptual change will no longer focus on science but on conceptual change in childhood. Are there any major obstacles to this bracing prospect? The main target of Gopnik and Meltzoff s book is cognitive development in the human child. Yet cognitive development in non-human primates displays several of the key features that they see as symptomatic of a theoretically oriented creature. To take one example, in some classic early experiments on search in the late 1920s, Otto Tinklepaugh established that monkeys would retrieve a piece of banana that they had seen placed in a box, even after a delay. In a variant of the standard task, Tinklepaugh surreptitiously removed the banana during the wait period, substituted a much less desirable piece of lettuce, and watched what happened. The puzzlement and anger of the animals when they discovered that the box contained only lettuce testified to their belief in object permanence. More generally, the development of search in non-human primates displays the sequence of errors and improvements that is found among human infants. Using Gopnik and Meltzoff's criteria, then, it is not just human children but also non-human primates that are theoretically minded. On one reading of Gopnik and Meltzoff's thesis, this conclusion is unproblematic. There is no particular reason for assuming that only human beings are capable of theory-like change in their thinking. Moreover, the empirical study of such cognitive change might benefit from a comparative dimension. Thus, we might conclude that institutionalized science fuses a natural theoretical capacity that is found in the young of various species with other specifically human practices and beliefs. By implication, if we want to understand conceptual change. we had better study it in its most natural form — in young primates, human and non-human. If we focus on conceptual change in science, we may be distracted by various cultural artefacts that sometimes bolster but also obscure the natural cognitive process. However, one might also draw a different conclusion from the primate evidence. Arguably, institutionalized science is underpinned by cognitive capacities that are distinctive among human beings, particularly children. On this argument, although primates may display those features of the theoretical mode that are emphasized by Gopnik and Meltzoff, there are likely to be other distinctively human features of that mode. Here is one speculative suggestion: unlike non-human primates, human children have a strong natural disposition to attribute observable actions — including simple acts such as reaching for an object — to hidden forces, notably beliefs, desires or intentions. More specifically, this early common-sense appreciation of psychological states involves a different kind of explanatory move from anything found in naive physics. The proposed causal powers — namely mental states — are ontologically distinct from what they are supposed to explain — namely actions and utterances. In naive physics, by contrast, the postulate of a permanent, enduring object is ontologically continuous with what it is supposed to explain, namely the object that reappears after a temporary disappearance. The disposition to postulate distinctive hidden powers might lead you to invoke gravity, alchemical forces, a deus ex machina, or all three. This line of argument implies that the study of cognitive development will offer a new perspective not just on science, but also on magic and religion,. In short, the alternative to Gopnik and Meltzoff may be even more bracing than the agenda that they have in mind. Either way, they are to be applauded for writing a book which is infectiously ambitious, even as they keep their feet on the ground.The Times Literary Supplement June 13, 1997
Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

Series Foreword
Preface and Acknowledgments
1 The Other Socratic Method 1
2 The Scientist as Child 13
3 Theories, Modules, and Empirical Generalizations 49
4 The Child's Theory of Appearances 77
5 The Child's Theory of Action 125
6 The Child's Theory of Kinds 161
7 Language and Thought 189
8 The Darwinian Conclusion 211
Notes 225
References 229
Index 251
Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Be the first to write a review
( 0 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(0)

4 Star

(0)

3 Star

(0)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(0)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously

    If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
    Why is this product inappropriate?
    Comments (optional)