ISBN-10:
1607320983
ISBN-13:
9781607320982
Pub. Date:
03/16/2011
Publisher:
University Press of Colorado
Neurobehavioral Anatomy / Edition 3

Neurobehavioral Anatomy / Edition 3

by Christopher M. Filley

Paperback

View All Available Formats & Editions
Current price is , Original price is $34.95. You
Select a Purchase Option
  • purchase options
    $31.45 $34.95 Save 10% Current price is $31.45, Original price is $34.95. You Save 10%.
  • purchase options

Overview

Neurobehavioral Anatomy / Edition 3


Thoroughly revised and updated to reflect key advances in behavioral neurology, Neurobehavioral Anatomy, Third Edition is a clinically based account of the neuroanatomy of human behavior centered on a consideration of behavioral dysfunction caused by disorders of the brain. A concise introduction to brain-behavior relationships that enhances patient care and assists medical students, the book also serves as a handy reference to researchers, neuroscientists, psychiatrists, and geriatricians.

The book outlines how cognitive and emotional functions are represented and organized in the brain to produce the behaviors regarded as uniquely human. It reviews the effects of focal and diffuse brain lesions, and from this analysis a conception of the normal operations of the healthy brain emerges. Christopher M. Filley integrates data and material from different disciplines to create a concise and accessible synthesis that informs the clinical understanding of brain-behavior relationships. Clinically practical and theoretically stimulating, the book is an invaluable resource for those involved in the clinical care and study of people with neurobehavioral disorders.

Including a useful glossary and extensive references guiding users to further research, the third edition will be of significance to medical students, residents, fellows, practicing physicians, and the general reader interested in neurology.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9781607320982
Publisher: University Press of Colorado
Publication date: 03/16/2011
Pages: 304
Product dimensions: 6.00(w) x 8.90(h) x 0.70(d)

About the Author


Christopher M. Filley, M.D., is Director of the Behavioral Neurology Section and Professor of Neurology and Psychiatry at the University of Colorado School of Medicine. He is also Attending Neurologist at the Denver Veterans Affairs Medical Center.

Read an Excerpt

Neurobehavioral Anatomy


By Christopher M. Filley

University Press of Colorado

Copyright © 2011 University Press of Colorado
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-1-60732-098-2



CHAPTER 1

BEHAVIOR AND THE BRAIN


Human behavior has an enduring appeal. Who among us has not reflected from time to time on how it is that a memory is formed, a sentence produced, or an emotion experienced? What is the origin of the thoughts and feelings that seem so distinctively to characterize the human species? Despite the enormous interest of this subject, however, our knowledge of human behavior is remarkably limited. The principle that the brain is the source of behavior has been acknowledged — with some notable exceptions — since the time of Hippocrates in ancient Greece, but the study of this relatively small organ encased in the skull presents challenges like none other in human biology. Many scientific investigators are deterred by the extraordinary complexity of brain-behavior relationships and, thus, select other areas of inquiry in which meaningful advances — and research grants — are assumed to be more easily attainable. Much of the formal study of behavior is descriptive, and even at this level there are formidable difficulties in the reliable characterization of the observed phenomena. Correlating the vast expanse of human behavior with the intricate neurobiology of the brain in health and disease is still more imposing. This state of relative ignorance is particularly regrettable since a better understanding of behavior could provide limitless benefits both in enhancing the achievements of our species and in reducing its destructiveness. Indeed, a more complete view of behavior as a function of the brain would have important implications for every realm of human activity.

By way of introduction to the core information presented in this book, it will be useful first to consider some philosophical and historical background that influences the study of behavior. Then follows a discussion of selected features of brain anatomy that pertain to neurobehavioral function in general. A brief digression into the intriguing but discredited area of phrenology is then presented as an illustration of the perils of simplistic thinking. Finally, we consider behavioral neurology and its unique viewpoint, hoping to demonstrate how knowledge of brain structure and function is critical to a comprehensive understanding of human behavior.


The Mind-Brain Problem

Traditionally, philosophers have taken a primary role in considering the phenomena of human behavior. The introspective method of thinking about one's own thoughts and feelings was the sole available technique throughout most of human history. Scientific investigation of how and why people act as they do has a rather short history. Only in recent times has there been the development of a systematic empirical approach to the study of behavior, first with the rise of psychology in the nineteenth century (James 1890), and then with the explosive growth of neuroscience in the twentieth (Corsi 1991). These two traditions can be seen as "top down" and "bottom up" to signify their different approaches, and both have made major contributions to our understanding of behavior. Yet it hardly need be stated that these empirical endeavors have not laid to rest ancient philosophical issues. Science has by no means provided answers to all questions about the nature of the mind, and some would maintain that it never can (Horgan 1994). Biology can, however, provide provocative information with which to explore these issues. Although it may seem imprudent for a clinical neuroscientist to indulge in the discussion that follows, there is good reason to suppose that old philosophical problems can be more clearly addressed in the light of new biological knowledge (Young 1987).

One of the oldest and most difficult questions in philosophy is that of the relation of mind to body, commonly known as the mind-body problem. Human beings can reasonably assume that there exists, by virtue of daily experience, a conscious mind and, because of equally evident physical realities, an entity known as the body Of all body parts, it is also apparent that the brain very likely has the most to do with the mind, and the issue is therefore more precisely called the mind-brain problem. The difficulty arises when one realizes that mental states are clearly subjective, whereas the brain is an objective reality. Consciousness, to most people an obvious, albeit mysterious, human characteristic, does not readily appear to spring from the physical object we recognize as the brain. Many question whether a collection of nerve cells and chemicals can explain the ineffable phenomenon of consciousness, which is often equated with or regarded as akin to such concepts as the soul or spirit. As the philosopher John Searle bluntly poses the mind-brain problem: "How, for example, could this grey and white gook inside my skull be conscious?" (Searle 1984, 15). Consciousness does indeed appear to be the most mystifying feature of the human mind, and establishing it as a property of the brain is by no means straightforward.

Two fundamental solutions have dominated philosophical inquiry into this dilemma. For the sake of simplicity, these may be termed dualism and materialism. Dualism, most notably propounded by René Descartes in the seventeenth century, holds that mind and brain are independent; the famous Cogito ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am") asserts the primacy of mind over matter (Descartes 1637) and implies that mental activities are divorced from physical events. Descartes did imagine there to be a point of intersection between the mind and the body and suggested the unpaired pineal gland as the site where the mind receives sensory traffic and acts upon the brain. But his steadfast separation of the immaterial mind from the material brain has exerted enormous influence for hundreds of years.

Materialism, advanced in various ways by thinkers as diverse as John Locke, Bertrand Russell, and Francis Crick, contends in general that mind and body are inseparable; as a result, mental events are nothing more than the expression of the brain's physical activities. Advocates of this "identity theory" argue that the Cartesian division between mental and physical substances is no more than an assertion, in the trenchant phrase of Gilbert Ryle, that there exists a "ghost in the machine" (Ryle 1949). An extreme variant of materialism is B. F. Skinner's behaviorism, an influential movement in twentieth-century American psychology emphasizing the manipulation of behavior by environmental conditions (Skinner 1971), and which, in effect, holds the concept of mind to be irrelevant to the scientific study of behavior.

The mind-brain problem continues to be pursued with vigor. Among modern philosophers who have continued the debate are Karl Popper (Popper and Eccles 1977), an advocate of dualist interactionism, and those who reject dualism, such as Searle (1984, 2004), Patricia Churchland (1986), and Daniel Dennett (1991). In particular, Churchland and Dennett have embraced neuroscience to the extent that they employ the term "mind-brain" to express complete acceptance of the identity of mind and brain (Churchland 1986; Dennett 1991).

At first glance, the dualist position may seem untenable in view of modern conceptions of neuroscience, but difficult problems remain nonetheless. Prominent among them is the question of free will. Do people act "freely" or under strictly determined laws of physics and chemistry? This dilemma can be more precisely posed as follows: If the mind and brain are in fact identical, and the actions of the brain can eventually be understood and predicted, then where is an escape from the determinist trap into which materialism must fall? Will not all behavior be governed by physical forces, and thus free will be impossible? Here are other questions to which science has not yet offered an answer. Arguments such as these continue to pose for some a significant obstacle to an enthusiastic acceptance of the materialist position.

Notwithstanding the lingering uncertainties raised by dualism, it is difficult to deny the practical utility of the materialist perspective. Advances in science are no less impressive if they pertain to the neural basis of behavior than if they lead to the discovery of penicillin for the treatment of bacterial pneumonia. It is undeniable that investigation of the brain has informed the understanding of a wide range of human behaviors that were previously inexplicable as physical phenomena. In clinical practice, experience with stroke, dementia, or traumatic brain injury patients leaves little doubt that activities of the mind are reliably and often dramatically affected by physical alterations in the brain. The fact that uncertain or inconsistent relationships between brain and behavior continue to challenge neuroscientists — as they clearly do — is testimony to the extraordinary complexity of the brain, not evidence that such relationships do not exist. Although occasional neuroscientists can be found who adopt a dualist position (Penfield 1975; Popper and Eccles 1977), the great majority find that physical events are providing increasingly complete and satisfying explanations for the activities of the mind. As a heuristic principle, the notion that brain events underlie and are directly correlated with mental events has been remarkably productive to date. Without necessarily presuming to answer the thorny philosophical questions introduced above, neuroscience has nevertheless assembled an impressive body of data indicating that the mind's activities are an unequivocal result of the brain's structure and function. In this sense, scientific advances shed light on old problems that, while not solved, at least seem less imposing.

The position taken in these pages derives from an unhesitating embrace of the methods and findings of neuroscience, and therefore follows in the materialist tradition. Although neuroscience cannot comment on a nonphysical reality, there seems little to gain by postulating a spiritual or mystical essence that cannot be reduced to the level of scientific analysis, especially when such complex human capacities as memory, language, and emotion are already yielding to this kind of inquiry. Indeed, as we will see in Chapter 9, a neurology of religion is a plausible approach to understanding a human experience that has traditionally been seen as representing divine influence (Saver and Rabin 1997). In this respect, the dualist tradition does remind us that many mental events have been interpreted as dissociated from any apparent physical basis. Because the task ahead requires developing an understanding of how these mental events are organized by the brain, Searle has recently proposed the idea of "biological naturalism" as a perhaps more harmonious solution to the mind-brain problem (Searle 2004). Whatever the terminology preferred, the proposition that mental events are in fact caused by neurobiological processes in the brain has a compelling rationale and much empirical support (Geschwind 1985; Churchland 1986; Dennett 1991; Searle 2004), and there is ample reason to expect that continuing explication of the brain's operations will also unravel the secrets of the mind.


General Features of Brain Anatomy

Neuroanatomy has been a foundation of behavioral neurology and continues to provide many insights into the neural organization of human behavior. Just as the elemental motor and sensory functions of the nervous system can be understood as emanating from the operations of brain neurons, so too can the myriad phenomena of cognition and emotion (Mesulam 2000; Kandel, Schwartz, and Jessell 2000). This book is concerned with the anatomy of higher functions, and clinically relevant regions of the brain will be covered in the chapters that follow. As an introduction, however, it will be helpful to begin with some general neuroanatomic features of the brain as they bear upon neurobehavioral concepts; complete accounts of neuroanatomy can be found elsewhere (Nauta and Fiertag 1986; Parent 1996; Nolte 2002).

The human brain is a soft, gelatinous collection of gray and white matter encased in the cranium and weighing about 1,400 grams (roughly three pounds) in the adult. Estimates vary, but there may be 100 billion or more neurons in the brain, and at least ten times this number of glial cells (Kandel, Schwartz, and Jessell 2000). As an indicator of the astonishing degree of connectivity between cerebral neurons, each one makes contact with as many as 10,000 others (Kandel, Schwartz, and Jessell 2000). Interneurons, situated between afferent and efferent neurons, constitute by far the largest class of brain neurons, so that the great majority of the brain's neuronal activity is concerned with the processing and transfer of information that occur between sensory input and motor output (Kandel, Schwartz, and Jessell 2000). In other words, a large quantity of nervous tissue lies interposed between the sensory and motor systems to elaborate the phenomena of behavior.

The brain is made up of the cerebrum, the brainstem, and the cerebellum (Figures 1.1 and 1.2). Most important for the higher functions is the cerebrum, which comprises the paired cerebral hemispheres and the diencephalon, the main components of which are the thalamus and hypothalamus. Why the hemispheres are paired, and why they have distinct functional affiliations in contrast to other paired organs in the body such as the lungs and kidneys, are not understood, but the distinct operations of the two cerebral hemispheres will be frequently emphasized in this book. The hemispheres are folded into ridges called gyri, and the grooves between these are known as sulci or fissures. These gross neuroanatomical features form the basis for the division of the hemispheres into four lobes: frontal, temporal, parietal, and occipital.

The parcellation of the hemispheres into four lobes is somewhat arbitrary but serves to produce convenient neuroanatomical landmarks that have important functional affiliations. Table 1.1 gives a brief outline of some prominent brain-behavior relationships, which will be developed in greater detail throughout this book. The frontal lobes, largest and most anterior, provide the origin of the motor system via the corticospinal tracts, mediate the production of language and prosody, and organize the integrative capacities of motivation, comportment, and executive function. The temporal lobes receive primary auditory input, mediate comprehension of language and prosody, and, in concert with the closely connected limbic system, subserve important aspects of memory and emotion. The parietal lobes receive tactile input, mediate visuospatial competence, and subserve reading and calculation skills. The occipital lobes, smallest and most posterior, receive primary visual input and mediate perception of visual material before further processing occurs in more anterior regions.

The hemispheres are connected to each other primarily by the corpus callosum, a massive white matter tract containing some 300 million axons (Nolte 2002; Figure 1.2). This structure permits the continuous interhemispheric exchange of information and joins many distant but homologous cerebral areas into functionally unified networks. The diencephalon is found deep in the brain and has a major role in sensory, motor, arousal, and limbic activities. Within the diencephalon, the egg-shaped thalamus serves as a central relay station for all sensory systems with the exception of olfaction and has a critical role in wakefulness. The tiny hypothalamus exerts enormous influence through its control of the autonomic nervous system, with its sympathetic and parasympathetic divisions, and through its connections with the pituitary gland that enable the neural control of the endocrine system. In posterior and inferior regions of the brain lie the brainstem and the cerebellum. The brainstem, made up of the midbrain, pons, and medulla, plays an essential role in motor and sensory function, and the caudal brainstem contains centers for the control of respiration and cardiac function. The cerebellum acts in combination with gray matter nuclei in the hemispheres and the brainstem known as the basal ganglia (caudate, putamen, globus pallidus, and substantia nigra) to enable fine motor coordination and postural control. At the base of the brain, the medulla exits the skull through the foramen magnum, where it merges with the spinal cord, the most caudal portion of the central nervous system (CNS).

The brain is housed within and protected by the skull, and between the brain and the skull are three membranes: the dura mater, the arachnoid, and the pia mater. Within the subarachnoid space, cerebrospinal fluid (CSF) envelops the entire CNS and provides a buoyancy that adds further protection. The CSF is continually produced within the four ventricles of the brain — the paired lateral ventricles in the hemispheres, the third ventricle situated between the two thalami, and the fourth ventricle between the cerebellum and the brainstem — and enters the subarachnoid space through apertures in the fourth ventricle. Eventually the CSF circulates to the vertex of the brain and is absorbed into the venous system through the arachnoid villi. The ventricular system and the CSF are important for the structural support of the brain and for its metabolic activity as well.


(Continues...)

Excerpted from Neurobehavioral Anatomy by Christopher M. Filley. Copyright © 2011 University Press of Colorado. Excerpted by permission of University Press of Colorado.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Preface to the Third Edition XI

Chapter 1 Behavior and the Brain 1

The Mind-Brain Problem 2

General Features of Brain Anatomy 5

The Excesses of Phrenology 13

Behavioral Neurology 14

References 21

Chapter 2 Mental Status Evaluation 25

History and Interview 25

Mental Status Examination 28

Standardized Mental Status Testing 40

References 44

Chapter 3 Disorders of Arousal and Attention 49

Arousal Dysfunction 51

Attentional Dysfunction 54

References 60

Chapter 4 Memory Disorders 63

Inattention 64

Amnesia 65

Remote Memory Loss 71

References 72

Chapter 5 Language Disorders 75

Cerebral Dominance and Handedness 78

Aphasia 80

Alexia 86

Agraphia 89

References 90

Chapter 6 Apraxia 95

Limb Kinetic Apraxia 97

Ideomotor Apraxia 97

Ideational Apraxia 101

References 102

Chapter 7 Agnosia 105

Visual Agnosia 107

Auditory Agnosia 112

Tactile Agnosia 113

References 114

Chapter 8 Right Hemisphere Syndromes 119

Constructional Apraxia 120

Neglect 121

Spatial Disorientation 124

Dressing Apraxia 124

Aprosody 125

Amusia 127

Emotional Disorders 129

References 134

Chapter 9 Temporal Lobe Syndromes 139

The Limbic System 140

Temporal Lobe Epilepsy 143

Psychosis in Temporal Lobe Epilepsy 147

Temporal Lobe Epilepsy Personality 150

References 155

Chapter 10 Frontal Lobe Syndromes 159

Orbitofrontal Syndrome 163

Dorsolateral Syndrome 166

Medial Frontal Syndrome 167

Functions of the Frontal Lobes 168

References 172

Chapter 11 Traumatic Brain Injury 175

Focal Lesions 176

Diffuse Lesions 178

References 185

Chapter 12 Dementia 189

Cortical Dementias 194

Subcortical Dementias 200

White Matter Dementias 205

Mixed Dementias 214

References 218

Epilogue 227

Glossary of Neurobehavioral Terms 229

Index 241

Customer Reviews

Most Helpful Customer Reviews

See All Customer Reviews