Self Comes to Mind: Constructing the Conscious Brain [NOOK Book]

Overview

From one of the most significant neuroscientists at work today, a pathbreaking investigation of a question that has confounded philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists for centuries: how is consciousness created?
 
Antonio Damasio has spent the past thirty years studying and writing about how the brain operates, and his work has garnered acclaim for its singular melding of the scientific and the humanistic. In Self Comes to Mind, ...

See more details below
Self Comes to Mind: Constructing the Conscious Brain

Available on NOOK devices and apps  
  • NOOK Devices
  • NOOK HD/HD+ Tablet
  • NOOK
  • NOOK Color
  • NOOK Tablet
  • Tablet/Phone
  • NOOK for Windows 8 Tablet
  • NOOK for iOS
  • NOOK for Android
  • NOOK Kids for iPad
  • PC/Mac
  • NOOK for Windows 8
  • NOOK for PC
  • NOOK for Mac
  • NOOK Study
  • NOOK for Web

Want a NOOK? Explore Now

NOOK Book (eBook)
$13.99
BN.com price

Overview

From one of the most significant neuroscientists at work today, a pathbreaking investigation of a question that has confounded philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists for centuries: how is consciousness created?
 
Antonio Damasio has spent the past thirty years studying and writing about how the brain operates, and his work has garnered acclaim for its singular melding of the scientific and the humanistic. In Self Comes to Mind, he goes against the long-standing idea that consciousness is somehow separate from the body, presenting compelling new scientific evidence that consciousness—what we think of as a mind with a self—is to begin with a biological process created by a living organism. Besides the three traditional perspectives used to study the mind (the introspective, the behavioral, and the neurological), Damasio introduces an evolutionary perspective that entails a radical change in the way the history of conscious minds is viewed and told. He also advances a radical hypothesis regarding the origins and varieties of feelings, which is central to his framework for the biological construction of consciousness: feelings are grounded in a near fusion of body and brain networks, and first emerge from the historically old and humble brain stem rather than from the modern cerebral cortex.
 
Damasio suggests that the brain’s development of a human self becomes a challenge to nature’s indifference and opens the way for the appearance of culture, a radical break in the course of evolution and the source of a new level of life regulation—sociocultural homeostasis. He leaves no doubt that the blueprint for the work-in-progress he calls sociocultural homeostasis is the genetically well-established basic homeostasis, the curator of value that has been present in simple life-forms for billions of years. Self Comes to Mind is a groundbreaking journey into the neurobiological foundations of mind and self.

From the Hardcover edition.

Read More Show Less

Editorial Reviews

From Barnes & Noble

Dr. Antonio Damassio heads the University of Southern California's prestigious Brain and Creativity Institute, but readers know him best as the author of Descartes' Error and Looking for Spinoza, explorations of cutting-edge neuroscience that use the ideas of major thinkers as jumping-off points. Self Comes to Mind, perhaps his most ambitious book yet, tackles a central, age-old question: How is consciousness created? On that conundrum, Damassio offers a radical evolutionary perspective, arguing that consciousness is a biological process created by the brain. A refreshing way to explaining who we understand ourselves to be.

Publishers Weekly
As he has done previously, USC neuroscientist Damasio (Descartes' Error) explores the process that leads to consciousness. And as he has also done previously, he alternates between some exquisite passages that represent the best popular science has to offer and some technical verbiage that few will be able to follow. He draws meaningful distinctions among points on the continuum from brain to mind, consciousness to self, constantly attempting to understand the evolutionary reasons why each arose and attempting to tie each to an underlying physical reality. Damasio goes to great lengths to explain that many species, such as social insects, have minds, but humans are distinguished by the "autobiographical self," which adds flexibility and creativity, and has led to the development of culture, a "radical novelty" in natural history. Damasio ends with a speculative chapter on the evolutionary process by which mind developed and then gave rise to self. In the Pleistocene, he suggests, humans developed emotive responses to shapes and sounds that helped lead to the development of the arts. Readers fascinated from both a philosophical and scientific perspective with the question of the relationships among brain, mind, and self will be rewarded for making the effort to follow Damasio's arguments. (Nov.)
From the Publisher

Self Comes to Mind is a Big Idea book penned by a luminous thinker. . . . [A] beautifully sprawling and marvelous work.” —The Dallas Morning News

“Will give pleasure to anyone interested in original thinking about the brain. . . . Breathtakingly original.” —Financial Times 
 
“Damasio introduces some novel ideas. . . . Intriguing.” —New Scientist

“Adventurous, courageous, and intelligent. Antonio Damasio is one of the leading workers in the field of consciousness research. . . . I have great admiration for this book and its author.” —John Searle, The New York Review of Books

“Damasio’s most  ambitious work yet. . . . A lucid and important work.” —Wired.com

“A very interesting book . . . cogent, painstaking, imaginative, knowledgeable, honest, and persuasive . . . Damasio’s quest is both thorough and comprehensive.” —New York Journal of Books

“Damasio’s continental European training sensitizes him to the reductionist traps that ensnare so many of his colleagues. His is the only one of the many consciousness books weighing down my shelves that feels it necessary to mention Freud’s . . . use of the term unconscious.” —The Guardian (Book of the Week)

“A delight. You will embark on an intellectual journey well worth the effort.” —The Wilson Quarterly
 
“Readers of [Damasio’s] earlier books will encounter again the clar­ity and the richness of a scientific theory nourished by the practice of the neurologist.” —L’Humanité (France)

“Some scientific heavyweights have dared approach consciousness. Among them, Antonio Damasio has the immense advantage of a dual knowledge of the human brain, as scientist and clinician. In Self Comes to Mind he gives us a fascinating window of this inter­face between the brain and the world, which is grounded in our own body.” —Le Figaro (France)

“The marvel of reading Damasio’s book is to be convinced one can follow the brain at work as it makes the private reality that is the deepest self.” —V. S. Naipaul, Nobel laureate and author of A Bend in the River

“Damasio makes a grand transition from higher- brain views of emotions to deeply evolutionary, lower- brain contributions to emotional, sensory, and homeostatic experiences. He affi rms that the roots of consciousness are affective and shared by our fellow animals. Damasio’s creative vision leads relentlessly toward a nat­ural understanding of the very font of being.” —Jaak Panksepp, author of Affective Neuroscience and Baily Endowed Chair for Animal Well- Being Science, Washington State University

“I was totally captivated by Self Comes to Mind. Damasio presents his seminal discoveries in the fi eld of neuroscience in the broader contexts of evolutionary biology and cultural development. This trailblazing book gives us a new way of thinking about ourselves, our history, and the importance of culture in shaping our common future.” —Yo-Yo Ma

Kirkus Reviews

Damasio (Director/Univ. of Southern California Brain and Creativity Inst.; Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain, 2003, etc.) seeks to understand "the mystery of consciousness."

"Consciousness is a state of mind in which there is knowledge of one's own existence and of the existence of surroundings"—i.e., where the self introduces the property of subjectivity to the mix. The mind emerges as it composes patterns, "mapping" the world as it interacts with it, just as it maps its own processes. It will appropriate the sensory experiences and make them its own. "Ultimately consciousness allows us to perceive maps as images," writes Damasio, "to manipulate those images, and to apply reasoning to them." The author entertains the unconventional idea that mind processing begins at the brain-stem level, not in the cerebral cortex alone, and charts the interaction of the brain stem, the cerebral cortex and the thalamus, taking elementary mind processes through to imagination, reasoning and eventually language. He provides a well-rendered explanation for the role of consciousness in the natural selection of evolution by meeting an organism's needs through orientation and organization. Along the way, Damasio confronts such slippery characters as feelings, emotions, the will to prevail, biological value and homeostasis, and he also looks carefully at neuroanatomical reference. Consciousness, in the author's well-tempered and rangy explication, "resembles the execution of a symphony of Mahlerian proportions. But the marvel...is that the score and the conductor become reality only as life unfolds." And its many players are responsible for everything from internal housekeeping to "placing the self in an evanescent here and now, between a thoroughly lived past and an anticipated future, perpetually buffeted between the spent yesterdays and the tomorrows that are nothing but possibilities."

Awareness may be mostly mystery, but Damasio shapes its hints and glimmerings into an imaginative, informed narrative.

The Barnes & Noble Review

From A. C. Grayling's "THE THINKING READ" column on The Barnes & Noble Review


Antonio Damasio has a remarkable scientific imagination and an admirable literary style. The combination makes for fascinating reading. From the clinical data and the neuropsychological experimental work that has gathered both pace and precision in recent years, he draws compelling insights, forming a map of possibilities about the nature of that ultimate mystery, consciousness. He writes with such flair and confidence that it is almost as if he makes the mystery dissolve into knowledge before our eyes.

But there is a large caveat about the brilliant display to be found in his latest work: there is such a meld of speculation, controversial inference, hypothesis, and fiat among his reports of clinical and experimental findings that one quickly feels ("feeling" being a big cognitive enchilada for Damasio) insecure about the value of what one is reading. It is a feeling that should quickly transform into recognition, though, that Damasio is deliberately in the business of imagining an entire psychoneurology, a total explanatory picture of the way consciousness arises as the gift of a knowing, reflexive self. He offers us a grand "think of it this way," comparable perhaps to the picture of the world that Cristofero Colombus had in mind when he set sail. Cristofero had and Antonio has, each of them, one big thing right -- the former that the earth is round, the latter that the phenomena of mind and consciousness are operations of the brain and nothing other than that. But neither yet knew what lies in the path of a journey to their Indies.

And this, of course, Damasio acknowledges. But he says, "Nonetheless, at one's own peril, it is reasonable to think through the questions and use the current evidence, incomplete and provisional as it is, to build testable conjectures and dream about the future."

If his conjectures and dreams are right, Damasio has told us what consciousness is and how it came to be -- and even, indeed, which brain structures are principally involved in its generation. He does not, however, as no one yet does, claim to say how the phenomenology and felt quality of consciousness is secreted by the millions of interacting neurons in those structures. That is the Indies of this great scientific voyage, and no amount of ingenious speculation about brain structures and their experimentally established correlations with arousal, emotion, memory, integration of sensory data, reasoning, language capability, and the rest, yet reaches it.

Damasio says that his new book, Self Comes to Mind, was written in order to "start over." In previous works for the general public, Descartes' Error and The Feeling of What Happens, he argued that emotion is essential to reason -- thus overturning the view, as old as Aristotle, that reason and emotion are at odds -- and that emotion is essential also to "homeostatic regulation," the process by which a system maintains itself in a stable condition through continual self-monitoring and adjustment. In those books and in technical papers Damasio advanced his "somatic marker" hypothesis to explain how emotion underpins ratiocination: bodily feelings accompany our thoughts about the outcomes of a range of possible choices, he suggested, thus helping us to select one among them more efficiently. This idea has been influential and widely discussed in psychology and neurology.

In The Feeling of What Happens Damasio took further the idea that emotions are biologically-ordained neurochemical responses that exist to maintain homeostasis. "Feelings" are our conscious recognition of these emotions; they are, as he there described them, the "private, mental experience of an emotion," taking the form of images. The importance of this for Damasio is that consciousness requires a sense of self, whose source is the continual internal monitoring of somatic responses to the external world -- the adjustment of the lens of the eye, the neck muscles turning the head to look, and much more, all integrating into what he calls the "proto-self," the non-conscious mapping that enables homeostasis.

From this emerges the "core self," the moment-to-moment entity present as second-order awareness of every interaction between the individual and the objects it encounters; and this in turn underwrites the "autobiographical self," the self we are ordinarily familiar with. These ideas are couched in an extensive framework of concepts derived partly from clinical and experimental work on brain function, and partly from Damasio's genius for speculation.

But in the opening pages of his new book Damasio says, "I have grown dissatisfied with my account of the problem, and reflection on relevant research findings, new and old, has changed my views." His change of views relates to two topics in particular: the nature of feelings, and the "mechanisms behind the construction of the self."

The latter is the central point, because his earlier account of the proto-, core, and autobiographical selves received much detailed criticism, no doubt prompting the new version here. In "approaching the conscious mind, I privilege the self," Damasio writes. "I believe conscious minds arise when a self process is added onto a basic mind process. When selves do not occur within minds, those minds are not conscious in the proper sense." His talk of "process" is key. Self is a process, not a thing, and it is best considered from two standpoints. One is that of "an observer appreciating a dynamic object," this object being the mental workings, behaviour traits, and an autobiographical past. The other standpoint is "that of the self as knower, that process that gives a focus to our experiences and eventually lets us reflect on those experiences." The combination of the two perspectives "produces the dual notion of self used throughout this book," between them telling an evolutionary story about the development of selfhood, the self-as-knower arising from the self-as-object.

Damasio's work has always been richly influenced by his reading of philosophy, either in the negative sense of rejecting mind-body dualism -- of Descartes's "great error" -- or in profiting from the insights of Spinoza and, in this present book particularly, William James. Before a turf war arises over whether James (brother of the more famous Henry) was a philosopher or psychologist, one has to remember that in his day there was no difference. What Damasio especially appreciates in James is his view of the role of feelings in the reflexive awareness that constitutes selfhood. This is music to Damasio's ears, and marks a line of continuity with his earlier work. There can be no sense of self without a sense of separation from what is other; feelings -- which Damasio now calls "feelings of knowing" -- operate as markers distinguishing the self from what is nonself. "We shall see that the construction of mind depends, at several stages, on the generation of such feelings."

And then the crucial step takes place, from the idea of self-as-knower to Damasio's account of consciousness itself, which he defines as consisting of "an organization of mind contents centered on the organism that produces and motivates those contents," together with the self's knowing that it exists as such a thing. That makes consciousness the self-aware existence of the organization of "mind contents"; which is surely uncontroversial, though the novelty lies in the way Damsio puts the machine together.

Thus the case Damasio sets out at length and in detail. It advances beyond his earlier views by adapting and making more detailed use of the notions of feeling and selfhood than occurred there. It offers a picture of consciousness that is intuitively both plausible and appealing, but which -- as the book proceeds -- becomes increasingly suppositious on the technical question of the brain mechanisms involved and their psychological correlates. The experts will have plenty to wrestle with there.

But there should be consensus over Part IV of the book, "Long After Consciousness," where Damasio discusses the question of why consciousness evolved. That consensus should be that it is an imaginative and suggestive excursus in Damasio's best signature manner. In the course of it he introduces several striking notions, such as that of the "genomic unconscious," which is "the colossal number of instructions that are contained in our genome and that guide the construction of the organism with the distinctive features of our phenotype…and that further assist with the operation of the organism." Here is part of a story once told in terms of instinct, drives, and other unconscious forces. He speaks also of there being, at another level of the unconscious, "well-rehearsed" cognitive activities "trained under the supervision of conscious reflection to observe consciously conceived ideals, wants and plans." That is a good way of putting the point.

Culture, and with it such key notions as the idea of justice, are the outcomes of consciousness. Damasio makes interesting play with this. In asking why consciousness evolved, and answering that it contributes massively to many aspects of the management of life -- the larger homeostasis, one might say -- one thereby begins to give an account of the role of culture and the building of institutions. This follows the emergence of language, not possible without consciousness, and the capacity to retain and canvass memories, and to look into the future and plan.

Damasio sees this as the ultimate gift of consciousness to humanity: "the ability to navigate the future in the seas of our imagination, guiding the self craft into a safe and productive harbour." The interaction of self and feeling-shaped memory "is what allows humans to imagine both individual well-being and the compounded well-being of a whole society, and to invent ways and means of achieving and magnifying that well-being."

That is a compelling picture, once one sets aside the power of the unconscious, and of grasping, other-hating, defensive, anxious, ideologically-motivated consciousness, to go to war, and create weapons that destroy in seconds what was built over centuries: consciousness and selfhood are not automatically benign entities. But either way they might well have the roots Damasio traces them to, and perhaps even the physiological architecture he says underlies them. Taking his own strictures to heart, namely to remember that psychoneurology is at a very early stage of an immensely complicated investigation, what one has to applaud is the imaginative vision Damasio brings to the task.




Read More Show Less

Product Details

  • ISBN-13: 9780307379498
  • Publisher: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group
  • Publication date: 11/9/2010
  • Sold by: Random House
  • Format: eBook
  • Pages: 336
  • Sales rank: 441,695
  • File size: 4 MB

Meet the Author

Antonio Damasio is University Professor; David Dornsife Professor of Neuroscience, Neurology and Psychology; and director of the Brain and Creativity Institute at the University of Southern California [usc.edu/bci]. He is the author of numerous scientific articles and the recipient of many awards, including the Asturias Prize in Science and Technology; the Honda Prize; and the Pessoa and Signoret prizes. Damasio is a member of the Institute of Medicine of the National Academy of Sciences, and a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, the Bavarian Academy of Sciences, and the European Academy of Sciences and Arts. He holds honorary doctorates from several universities and is the author of Descartes’ Error, The Feeling of What Happens, Looking for Spinoza, and Self Comes to Mind, which have been translated and taught in universities throughout the world.
 
(For more information go to the Brain and Creativity Institute website at usc.edu/bci/)

From the Hardcover edition.

Read More Show Less

Read an Excerpt

1
 Awakening
 
When I woke up, we were descending. I had been asleep long enough to miss the announcements about the landing and the weather. I had not been aware of myself or my surroundings. I had been unconscious.
 
Few things about our biology are as seemingly trivial as this com­modity known as consciousness, the phenomenal ability that consists of having a mind equipped with an owner, a protagonist for one’s exis­tence, a self inspecting the world inside and around, an agent seemingly ready for action.
 
Consciousness is not merely wakefulness. When I woke up, two brief paragraphs ago, I did not look around vacantly, taking in the sights and the sounds as if my awake mind belonged to no one. On the con­trary, I knew, almost instantly, with little hesitation if any, without effort, that this was me, sitting on an airplane, my flying identity com­ing home to Los Angeles with a long  to-do list before the day would be over, aware of an odd combination of travel fatigue and enthusiasm for what was ahead, curious about the runway we would be landing on, and attentive to the adjustments of engine power that were bringing us to earth. No doubt, being awake was indispensable to this state, but wake­fulness was hardly its main feature. What was that main feature? The fact that the myriad contents displayed in my mind, regardless of how vivid or well ordered, connected with me, the proprietor of my mind, through invisible strings that brought those contents together in the forward-moving feast we call self; and, no less important, the fact that the connection was felt. There was a feelingness to the experience of the connected me.
 
Awakening meant having my temporarily absent mind returned, but with me in it, both property (the mind) and proprietor (me) accounted for. Awakening allowed me to reemerge and survey my mental domains, the sky-wide projection of a magic movie, part documentary and part fiction, otherwise known as the conscious human mind.
 
We all have free access to consciousness, bubbling so easily and abun­dantly in our minds that without hesitation or apprehension we let it be turned off every night when we go to sleep and allow it to return every morning when the alarm clock rings, at least 365 times a year, not counting naps. And yet few things about our beings are as remarkable, foundational, and seemingly mysterious as consciousness. Without consciousness—that is, a mind endowed with subjectivity—you would have no way of knowing that you exist, let alone know who you are and what you think. Had subjectivity not begun, even if very modestly at first, in living creatures far simpler than we are, memory and reasoning are not likely to have expanded in the prodigious way they did, and the evolutionary road for language and the elaborate human version of con­sciousness we now possess would not have been paved. Creativity would not have flourished. There would have been no song, no paint­ing, and no literature. Love would never have been love, just sex. Friendship would have been mere cooperative convenience. Pain would never have become suffering—not a bad thing, come to think of it— but an equivocal advantage given that pleasure would not have become bliss either. Had subjectivity not made its radical appearance, there would have been no knowing and no one to take notice, and conse­quently there would have been no history of what creatures did through the ages, no culture at all.
 
Although I have not yet provided a working definition of conscious­ness, I hope I am leaving no doubt as to what it means not to have con­sciousness: in the absence of consciousness, the personal view is sus­pended; we do not know of our existence; and we do not know that anything else exists. If consciousness had not developed in the course of evolution and expanded to its human version, the humanity we are now familiar with, in all its frailty and strength, would never have developed either. One shudders to think that a simple turn not taken might have meant the loss of the biological alternatives that make us truly human. But then, how would we ever have found out that something was missing?
 
We take consciousness for granted because it is so available, so easy to use, so elegant in its daily disappearing and reappearing acts, and yet, when we think of it, scientists and nonscientists alike, we do puzzle. What is consciousness made of? Mind with a twist, it seems to me, since we cannot be conscious without having a mind to be conscious of. But what is mind made of? Does mind come from the air or from the body? Smart people say it comes from the brain, that it is in the brain, but that is not a satisfactory reply. How does the brain do mind?
 
The fact that no one sees the minds of others, conscious or not, is especially mysterious. We can observe their bodies and their actions, what they do or say or write, and we can make informed guesses about what they think. But we cannot observe their minds, and only we our­selves can observe ours, from the inside, and through a rather narrow window. The properties of minds, let alone conscious minds, appear to be so radically different from those of visible living matter that thoughtful folk wonder how one process (conscious minds working) meshes with the other process (physical cells living together in aggre­gates called tissues).
 
But to say that conscious minds are mysterious—and on the face of it they are—is different from saying that the mystery is insoluble. It is dif­ferent from saying that we shall never be able to understand how a liv­ing organism endowed with a brain develops a conscious mind.

From the Hardcover edition.

Read More Show Less

Table of Contents

PART I STARTING OVER

1 Awakening 3

Goals and Reasons

Approaching the Problem

The Self as Witness

Overcoming a Misleading Intuition

An Integrated Perspective

The Framework

A Preview of Main Ideas

Life and the Conscious Mind

2 From Life Regulation to Biological Value 31

The Implausibility of Reality

Natural Will

Staying Alive

The Origins of Homeostasis

Cells, Multicellular Organisms, and Engineered Machines

Biological Value

Biological Value in Whole Organisms

The Success of Our Early Forerunners

Developing Incentives

Connecting Homeostasis, Value, and Consciousness

PART II WHAT'S IN A BRAIN THAT A MIND CAN BE?

3 Making Maps and Making Images 63

Maps and Images

Cutting Below the Surface

Maps and Minds

The Neurology of Mind

The Beginnings of Mind

Closer to the Making of Mind?

4 The Body in Mind 89

The Topic of the Mind

Body Mapping

From Body to Brain

Representing Quantities and Constructing Qualities

Primordial Feelings

Mapping Body States and Simulating Body States

The Source of an Idea

The Body-Minded Brain

5 Emotions and Feelings 108

Situating Emotion and Feeling

Defining Emotion and Feeling

Triggering and Executing Emotions

The Strange Case of William James

Feelings of Emotion

How Do We Feel an Emotion?

The Timing of Emotions and Feelings

The Varieties of Emotion

Up and Down the Emotional Range

An Aside on Admiration and Compassion

6 An Architecture for Memory 130

Somehow, Somewhere

The Nature of Memory Records

Dispositions Came First, Maps Followed

Memory at Work

A Brief Aside on Kinds of Memory

A Possible Solution to the Problem

More on Convergence-Divergence Zones

The Model at Work

The How and Where of Perception and Recall

PART III BEING CONSCIOUS

7 Consciousness Observed 157

Defining Consciousness

Breaking Consciousness Apart

Removing the Self and Keeping a Mind

Completing a Working Definition

Kinds of Consciousness

Human and Nonhuman Consciousness

What Consciousness is Not

The Freudian Unconscious

8 Building a Conscious Mind 180

A Working Hypothesis

Approaching the Conscious Brain

Previewing the Conscious Mind

The Ingredients of a Conscious Mind

The Protoself

Constructing the Core Self

The Core Self State

Touring the Brain as It Constructs a Conscious Mind

9 The Autobiographical Self 210

Memory Made Conscious

Constructing the Autobiographical Self

The Issue of Coordination

The Coordinators

A Possible Role for the Posteromedial Cortices

The PMCs at Work

Other Considerations on the Posteromedial Cortices

A Closing Note on the Pathologies of Consciousness

10 Putting It Together 241

By Way of Summary

The Neurology of Consciousness

The Anatomical Bottleneck Behind the Conscious Mind

From the Ensemble Work of Large Anatomical Divisions to the Work of Neurons

When We Feel Our Perceptions

Qualia I

Qualia II

Qualia and Self

Unfinished Business

PART IV LONG AFTER CONSCIOUSNESS

11 Living with Consciousness 267

Why Consciousness Prevailed

Self and the Issue of Control

An Aside on the Unconscious

A Note on the Genomic Unconscious

The Feeling of Conscious Will

Educating the Cognitive Unconscious

Brain and Justice

Nature and Culture

Self Comes to Mind

The Consequences of a Reflective Self

Appendix 299

Notes 319

Acknowledgments 343

Index 345

Read More Show Less

Customer Reviews

Average Rating 4
( 11 )
Rating Distribution

5 Star

(5)

4 Star

(3)

3 Star

(2)

2 Star

(0)

1 Star

(1)

Your Rating:

Your Name: Create a Pen Name or

Barnes & Noble.com Review Rules

Our reader reviews allow you to share your comments on titles you liked, or didn't, with others. By submitting an online review, you are representing to Barnes & Noble.com that all information contained in your review is original and accurate in all respects, and that the submission of such content by you and the posting of such content by Barnes & Noble.com does not and will not violate the rights of any third party. Please follow the rules below to help ensure that your review can be posted.

Reviews by Our Customers Under the Age of 13

We highly value and respect everyone's opinion concerning the titles we offer. However, we cannot allow persons under the age of 13 to have accounts at BN.com or to post customer reviews. Please see our Terms of Use for more details.

What to exclude from your review:

Please do not write about reviews, commentary, or information posted on the product page. If you see any errors in the information on the product page, please send us an email.

Reviews should not contain any of the following:

  • - HTML tags, profanity, obscenities, vulgarities, or comments that defame anyone
  • - Time-sensitive information such as tour dates, signings, lectures, etc.
  • - Single-word reviews. Other people will read your review to discover why you liked or didn't like the title. Be descriptive.
  • - Comments focusing on the author or that may ruin the ending for others
  • - Phone numbers, addresses, URLs
  • - Pricing and availability information or alternative ordering information
  • - Advertisements or commercial solicitation

Reminder:

  • - By submitting a review, you grant to Barnes & Noble.com and its sublicensees the royalty-free, perpetual, irrevocable right and license to use the review in accordance with the Barnes & Noble.com Terms of Use.
  • - Barnes & Noble.com reserves the right not to post any review -- particularly those that do not follow the terms and conditions of these Rules. Barnes & Noble.com also reserves the right to remove any review at any time without notice.
  • - See Terms of Use for other conditions and disclaimers.
Search for Products You'd Like to Recommend

Recommend other products that relate to your review. Just search for them below and share!

Create a Pen Name

Your Pen Name is your unique identity on BN.com. It will appear on the reviews you write and other website activities. Your Pen Name cannot be edited, changed or deleted once submitted.

 
Your Pen Name can be any combination of alphanumeric characters (plus - and _), and must be at least two characters long.

Continue Anonymously
Sort by: Showing all of 11 Customer Reviews
  • Posted August 31, 2011

    more from this reviewer

    Fascinating

    Damasio's passion for understanding the self is seen within the first few sentences of the text. If your looking for a book that doesn't beat around the bush and gets straight to the point. This is it.

    1 out of 2 people found this review helpful.

    Was this review helpful? Yes  No   Report this review
  • Anonymous

    Posted July 27, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted January 24, 2014

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted July 26, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted March 6, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted June 3, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted June 8, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted April 22, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted January 12, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted March 12, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

  • Anonymous

    Posted January 4, 2011

    No text was provided for this review.

Sort by: Showing all of 11 Customer Reviews

If you find inappropriate content, please report it to Barnes & Noble
Why is this product inappropriate?
Comments (optional)