Liberalism: The Life of an Idea, Second Edition

Liberalism: The Life of an Idea, Second Edition

by Edmund Fawcett
Liberalism: The Life of an Idea, Second Edition

Liberalism: The Life of an Idea, Second Edition

by Edmund Fawcett

Paperback(Second)

$27.95 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores

Related collections and offers


Overview

A compelling history of liberalism from the nineteenth century to today

Despite playing a decisive role in shaping the past two hundred years of American and European politics, liberalism is no longer the dominant force it once was. In this expanded and updated edition of what has become a classic history of liberalism, Edmund Fawcett traces its ideals, successes, and failures through the lives and ideas of exemplary thinkers and politicians from the early nineteenth century to today. Significant revisions—including a new conclusion—reflect recent changes affecting the world political order that many see as presenting new and very potent threats to the survival of liberal democracy as we know it. A richly detailed account of a vulnerable but critically important political creed, this book reminds us that to defend liberalism it is vital to understand its character and history.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780691180380
Publisher: Princeton University Press
Publication date: 05/22/2018
Edition description: Second
Pages: 536
Sales rank: 320,609
Product dimensions: 5.50(w) x 8.40(h) x 1.30(d)

About the Author

Edmund Fawcett worked at The Economist for more than three decades, serving as chief correspondent in Washington, Paris, and Berlin, as well as European and literary editor. His writing has also appeared in the New York Times, the Los Angeles Times, the Guardian, and the Times Literary Supplement, among other publications.

Read an Excerpt

CHAPTER 1

Historical Setting in the 1830s

Thrown into a World of Ceaseless Change

On April 12, 1835, Wilhelm von Humboldt — diplomat, linguist, advocate of universal education, and liberal pioneer — was buried beside his wife, Caroline, in a small plot overlooked by a statue of Hope in the park of their estate on the northwestern edge of Berlin. Through the oak trees lies Tegelsee, one of many lakes that give the city its sparkling light. A short walk away stands the family's elegant villa, rebuilt to a neoclassical design by Prussia's leading architect of the day, Karl-Friedrich Schinkel. The calm and seclusion give little clue that Humboldt lived in a world turned upside down. He was born into a Prussian noble family in 1767 before liberalism was dreamed of. By the time he died, revolutions in the Americas, the Dutch Republic, and France had shaken the Atlantic world and liberalism was on its way to becoming what it is today, a common practice of politics for market societies in perpetual motion.

At the time of Humboldt's birth in the court and barracks town of Potsdam to the southwest of the city, an enlightened warrior king, Frederick the Great, ruled Prussia, the American colonies were British, and the Bourbon monarchy ruled, or attempted to rule, France. Most Europeans lived and worked on the land near where they were born, dying as a rule before they were forty. Most could not read or write. In Britain four in ten men and seven in ten women could not sign their names at marriage. Urbanization, like industry, lay in the future. In the German Ruhr Valley, Düsseldorf was a tiny town and Essen little more than a village. London, Bristol, and a few small cities aside, England was a place of countryside and market towns. In a flash of scientific imagination, James Watt had grasped how an efficient piston might work, but a reliable steam engine had yet to be perfected and harnessed in industry. To satisfy a flourishing new social type, the middle-class shopper, Europe relied on trade and on slaves sold by Africans for work in New World colonies. Enlightenment thought thrived on hopes for human betterment but also on sugar, coffee, and tobacco.

Law and custom commonly limited where you could work or live, what associations you could form with like-minded friends or fellow workers, and what moneymaking enterprises you could start. Serfdom of a kind, tying laborers to their villages, survived in rural Prussia. Close to a quarter of Britain's two million American subjects were slaves or indentured servants working payless for a fixed term in return for their Atlantic passage and keep. Non-Anglicans could not teach in British schools or universities, nor marry legally without a vicar's dispensation. Catholics could not vote or sit in parliament. Jews in Britain, France, and Prussia lived on sufferance, without political or civil rights. Protections of speech and press were precarious. Prior censorship, where it existed, was spotty and haphazard, but the threat of reprisal was enough to make people think twice before speaking their minds. Punishments were frequently cruel and spectacular, especially if you were poor, defied power, or flouted orthodox opinion.

Such was the old world of Humboldt's birth in 1767. It was not as stunted or backward as critics made out. The world of Humboldt's birth was above all not fixed or frozen, but a world in movement. After centuries of creeping up and falling back, Europe's populations were exploding with growth. Pressure was on to find new ways to feed and provide for more people. The term would not be heard for another eighty years or so, but the first shoots of industrial capitalism — investing in productive machinery for private profit — were already visible. Pressure was also on to find new ways to do what wise and effective rulers had always done: listen to the people.

For voices were being raised against ills and encumbrances of the old world: against absolute and arbitrary monarchs, against backwardness, neglect, and illiteracy, against slavery and intolerance, against not being able to say and print what you wanted or make money as you pleased, against not having a voice. Established ethical authorities and accepted models of conduct, once as pervasive and weightless-seeming as air, felt suddenly burdensome and had to explain themselves. To practices and conditions previously taken for natural or irremovable there were, many now insisted, alternatives. There was, though, no one party of change, no one focus of opposition, no one vehicle of progress. There were in particular no liberals. In Humboldt's youth the word "liberal" meant generous, open-handed, or perhaps lenient to a fault. The phrase "a liberal" was a grammatical mistake and the term "liberalism" would have met blank stares. By the time of Humboldt's death, in a world transformed, a new approach to politics was emerging to welcome and, it was hoped, to channel breathtaking change.

Humboldt was too young and distant to witness the first great upheaval of his life, the American Revolution, when Britain's fractious New World colonies won a war of independence in 1783, imposed a disputed constitution on themselves and founded a divided, experimental new republic, the United States. For the lasting aftershocks of another upheaval, the French Revolution, Humboldt was present in person as a high official, diplomat, and liberal dissident in an enlightened but autocratic Prussian government.

In the summer of 1789 young Humboldt was on a European tour with his old tutor when news reached them of revolution in France. They rushed to Paris, and three weeks after its fall visited the Bastille, which workmen were beginning to demolish. The "grave of despotism," as the tutor solemnly put it, impressed them both, but the idea of revolution did not sweep young Humboldt away. He asked himself what revolution would do for the sick and poor of the city, whose condition appalled him. Nobody knew what lay ahead. In Paris, as on the rest of the trip, Humboldt mostly saw sights and visited brothels, carefully noting what he spent there in his day book.

Humboldt welcomed what he took for revolution's higher aims: an end to arbitrary rule and a historic release of human capacities; but he thought the means, rewriting society's ground rules, were sure to fail. Foreign invasion, civil war, counterinvasion, and state-led terror — against foes of revolution rich or poor and soon against any who murmured a word against terror — seemed to confirm Humboldt's worst fears. They left him also with a historic challenge. Revolution and war had shattered Europe's old political order. Humboldt's generation and those that followed faced a long search for a new one.

The French declared a republic, executed their Bourbon king for treason, won and lost again control of most of Europe under a corporal-turned-emperor, Napoleon Bonaparte, lived through fifteen years of reaction after his defeat in 1815, and then shook Europe a second time by throwing out a restored Bourbon monarchy in 1830. The British and Germans caught the mood. In November, the liberal Whigs replaced the conservative Tories in power after almost half a century in opposition, and an era of economic, social, and political reform began at Westminster. In the German lands — the nation was unified only in 1871 — absolute princes, whether despotic or enlightened, faced demands for civil liberties, constitutional rule, and representative government. Everywhere the brutalities and excesses of the old order began to pass. In the United States a wave of campaigning improvement, both political and moral, swept the fractious new republic. It took in many causes — temperance, women's rights, and slavery, the most divisive of all — but animating each of those causes was a fervent, often religious, conviction that American life on earth should be less wild, more orderly, and more reformed.

In Europe half a century of conservative attempts to sit on change, to maintain or restore the old order, was ending. Restrictions on speech, press, travel, residency, association, trade, commerce, and the public practice of religion came under challenge and were in many places lifted. In the new American republic, restrictions of like kind rejected in the federal constitution but surviving in state law or custom were by now also disappearing. It was a motley of causes pressed by clashing voices with rival interests and conflicting priorities. The word meant different things in different mouths. But a flag of convenience that swept up many of those separate causes was the banner term "liberty." A vast and loose party of movement began to form. Its followers started to call themselves liberals.

In 1835, the year Humboldt died, Germany's first steam train, the Adler, puffed up a section of line from Nuremberg to Fürth. That same year French navvies began laying railway track from Paris to the Atlantic port of Le Havre. Samuel Morse devised a code to shorten messages on the newly invented electric telegraph, and Samuel Colt took out a patent for his revolver. The German chemist Justus Liebig synthesized a precursor for the artificial material known as plastic, which before long would transform what people wore, sat on, and ate off. Plate-glass mirrors began to appear in ordinary homes and William Fox Talbot exposed the first photographic negatives, two devices that changed how people saw themselves and gave spurs to demanding new routines of self-improvement as well as to the fashion industry. Money was becoming an all-purpose solvent and a common standard of value. In France the Laffitte bank financed liberal ministries. The British state borrowed from the Rothschild Brothers to pay £20 million in compensation for "property" lost on the abolition of empire slavery the previous year. Bank of England notes became an unrefusable means of settlement in trade and were soon Britain's only legal tender. Factory production, with its rough standards but massive quantities, was replacing craft work. In 1835 there were fewer Prussian hatters per head of population than there had been in 1767, the year of Humboldt's birth, but many more new hats.

As the summer of 1835 ended, a Rhineland merchant's son entered the University of Bonn, where he threw himself into the drinking and gaming clubs. His father soon harried him to pursue serious studies at the new university that Humboldt had founded in Berlin. The boy was Karl Marx, and before long he would alter ideas about historical change. In September a British naval ship, HMS Beagle, carrying a naturalist on a four-year geological survey docked at the Galapagos Islands. He was Charles Darwin, and he would soon alter ideas about natural change. Marxism challenged inclusive liberal gradualism with a rival picture of historical progress as a sequence of dominant classes superseding one another. Darwinism, though not Darwin himself, tempted liberals to think of politics as a kind of biology.

In Boston in 1835, Ralph Waldo Emerson began a career as a lecturer preaching the higher values of self-cultivation in a grubbily commercial world. In Paris, Honoré de Balzac, a writer who professed to hate liberals but found their drive and sense of social freedom irresistible, published the first installment of Père Goriot, his novel of ambition, betrayal, hidden powers, and "egoism" in a suddenly fluid society. On a tour of America young Richard Cobden, the future British champion of free trade, decided that go-getting Americans had found the secret of a strong economy. On an equally enthusiastic German visit three years later Cobden would see nothing strange in rhapsodizing in a letter to his brother about Prussian government. A flourishing society, Cobden thought, needed both. Also in 1835, a young nobleman in France's prefectural service, Aléxis de Tocqueville, published the first part of Democracy in America, his puzzled reflections on a new country where he had seen firsthand a society turning its back on tradition, status, and privilege. Lucid about much else, on slavery Tocqueville's prose became opaque, though America's irrepressible conflict was stirring. In October a mob chased William Garrison, the abolitionist publisher of The Liberator, through the Boston streets.

CHAPTER 2

Guiding Thoughts from Founding Thinkers

Conflict, Resistance, Progress, and Respect

i. Humboldt and Constant: Releasing People's Capacities and Respecting Their Privacy

It is tempting to wonder how Humboldt would have responded to this new world had he lived on like his younger brother, the explorer and naturalist Alexander, into the 1850s. Though some have taken Humboldt for an open-minded but conservative friend of the old world, he voiced a conviction that runs like an arrow through nineteenth-century liberal thought. His leading idea — dashed off in a youthful essay, The Limits of the Effectiveness of the State (1792), but published in full only after his death — had a head and a tail, a positive and a negative part: developing human capacities to the full in their diversity and individuality was an urgent task, but a task for which laws, government, and regulation were generally inept.

For anyone who did not get past his essay's title, it was easy to miss what Humboldt was saying. He was not thinking so much of government intervention in markets as of how state and society, which were not distinct in his mind, could stifle the true end of human life: finding and making full use of your talents in your own way. Humboldt certainly took a narrow view of the state's capacities. It had a job, he wrote, to defend people ("negative welfare") but not to support them ("positive welfare"). The state's holding property was a poor idea, as it was virtually bound to end up owning too much, and there was no future in levying sales taxes, which cost almost as much as they brought in. To pay for tasks the state could and should carry out, defense and justice, it might on the other hand tax income. It should not try to improve morals and should leave private conscience alone, for Humboldt believed everyone should be able to follow whatever religion they chose, or none. Humboldt was open-minded about constitutions. Different ones suited different places. The key everywhere was to have a constitution with "the least possible positive or special influence on the character of the citizens." His friend and contemporary Benjamin Constant (1767–1830) echoed and amplified the protective, negative aspect of Humboldt's leading idea. In Principles of Politics (1815) Constant wrote, "There is a part of human existence that remains of necessity individual and independent, and which lies by right utterly beyond the range of society."

Clustered here in celebration of people's independence are thoughts that lie at the liberal core. The first is that everybody — but especially those with power — must respect the deep-held aims and beliefs of others and not intrude on them by imposing purposes and ideals people have not chosen for themselves. The second thought is that people have within them an open-ended capacity for betterment and reform: to grow, to improve, to progress, with help or direction from others if need be. Constant, a more laidback and permissive spirit, stressed more the first, nonintrusive thought. Humboldt, a born teacher, stressed the second, more educative thought. Though both men saw unique worth in people, Constant thought of that worth as something private that modern people now had ever more means to defend from intrusion; Humboldt saw it as a germ of potential to be cultivated and encouraged to grow. In theory both convictions — respect for personal privacy and zeal for human progress — sped together in parallel. In practice, they often got in each other's way, as liberals soon had to confront. Hardly a topic in nineteenth-century liberal thinking about politics did not turn in some way on the intrusive business of improving people's capacity to choose the aims of life well for themselves — on education that is, thought of in the broadest terms.

Both men were outsiders among insiders, Humboldt by temperament, Constant by temperament but also birth. Constant the man together with his defense of liberal privacy will appear in turn. We need to see first how, on turning from diplomacy to education, Humboldt put his ideals about nurturing human potential into practice.

After Prussia's capitulation to Napoleon's armies in 1806, Humboldt lost his post as envoy to the Holy See and soon left Rome, where for six years he had happily drunk in and written about the classical past. On return to chilly Berlin, he took charge of the section in the Interior Ministry that set up Europe's first full system of centrally administered state schools and founded a university teaching the nontechnical subjects of humanities and law. A strange step, you might think, for a pioneer liberal who insisted that the state was a "body of laws, not a school." Humboldt saw no conflict, for what mattered to him was the kind of school a state provided. Education that imposed purposes and limited choices should be discouraged, he believed, particularly if they were a state's purposes or those of its elites. With that in mind Humboldt tried, without success, to close Prussia's military academies and schools reserved for nobles. He opposed also vocational schools that taught chiefly crafts and trades. The trouble with them all in Humboldt's mind was that such schools aimed at a final product: soldier, state official, artisan. They narrowed life's choices. They put or kept people in boxes. He favored by contrast an open, nonimposing "liberal" education, rich in Greek and Latin, of the whole man, whatever he might turn out to be — women were not as yet part of the liberal story.

(Continues…)


Excerpted from "Liberalism"
by .
Copyright © 2018 Edmund Fawcett.
Excerpted by permission of PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Preface to the Second Edition xi

Acknowledgments xv

Introduction The Practice of Liberalism 1

Part 1 The Confidence of Youth (1830-1880)

1 Historical Setting in the 1830s: Thrown into a World of Ceaseless Change 33

2 Guiding Thoughts from Founding Thinkers: Conflict, Resistance, Progress, and Respect 39

i Humboldt and Constant: Releasing People's Capacities and Respecting Their Privacy 39

ii Guizot: Taming Conflict without Arbitrary Power 49

iii Tocqueville and Schulze-Delitzsch: The Modem Powers of Mass Democracy and Mass Markets 61

iv Chadwick and Cobden: Governments and Markets as Engines of Social Progress 69

v Smiles and Channing: Personal Progress as Self-Reliance or Moral Uplift 77

vi Spencer: Liberalism Mistaken for Biology 82

vii J. S. Mill; Holding Liberalism's Ideas Together 88

3 Liberalism in Practice: Four Exemplary Politicians 101

i Lincoln: The Many Uses of "Liberty" in the Land of Liberty 101

ii Laboulaye and Richter: Tests for Liberals in Semiliberal Regimes 108

iii Gladstone: Liberalism's Capaciousness and the Politics of Balance 115

4 The Nineteenth-Century Legacy: Liberalism without Caricature 120

i Respect, "the Individual," and the Lessons of Toleration 120

ii The Achievements That Gave Liberals Confidence 135

Part 2 Liberalism in Maturity and the Struggle with Democracy (1880-1945)

5 Historical Setting in the 1880s: The World Liberals Were Making 139

6 The Compromises That Gave Us Liberal Democracy 147

i Political Democracy: Liberal Resistance to Suffrage Extension 147

ii Economic Democracy. The "New Liberalism" and Novel Tasks for the State 160

iii Ethical Democracy: Letting Go Ethically and the Persistence of Intolerance 167

7 The Economic Powers of the Modern State and Modern Market 173

i Walras, Marshall, and the Business Press: Resisting the State on Behalf of Markets 173

ii Hobhouse, Naumann, Croly, and Bourgeois: Resisting Markets on Behalf of Society 186

8 Damaged Ideals and Broken Dreams 198

i Chamberlain and Bassennann: Liberal Imperialism 198

ii Lloyd George, Clemenceau, and Wilson: Liberal Hawks of 1914-1918 214

iii Alain, Baldwin, and Brandeis: Liberal Dissent and the Warfare State 226

iv Stresemann: Liberal Democracy in Peril 235

v Kermes, Fisher, and Hayek (i): Liberal Economists in the Slump 243

vi Hoover and Roosevelt: Forgotten Liberal and Foremost Liberal 264

9 Thinking about Liberalism in the 1930s-1940s 272

i Lippmann and Hayek (ii): Liberals as Antitotalitarians 272

ii Popper: Liberalism as Openness and Experiment 276

Part 3 Second Chance and Success (1945-1989)

10 Historical Setting after 1945: Liberal Democracy's New Start 283

11 New Foundations: Rights, a Democratic Rule of Law, and Welfare 287

i Drafters of the 1948 Declaration of Human Rights: Liberal Democracy Goes Global 287

ii German Postwar liberals: The 1.949 Basic Law as Liberal Democracy's Exemplary Charter 299

iii Beveridge: Liberalism and Welfare 308

12 Liberal Thinking after 1945 313

i Oakeshott and Berlin: Letting Politics Alone and "Negative" Liberty 314

ii Hayek (iii): Political Antipolitics 324

iii Orwell Camus, and Sartre: Liberals in the Cold War 328

iv Rawls: Justifying Liberalism 335

v Nozick, Dworkin, and MacIntyre: Responses to Rawls, Rights, and Community 345

13 The Breadth of Liberal Politics in the 1950s-1980s 352

i Mendès-France, Brandt, and Johnson: Left Liberalism in the 1950s-1960s 352

ii Buchanan and Friedman: Liberal Economists against the State 365

iii Thatcher, Reagan, Mitterrand, and Kohl: Right Liberalism in the 1970s-1980s 375

Part 4 Liberal Dreams and Nightmares in the Twenty-First Century

14 Two Decades That Shook Liberal Democracy 389

i The Rise of the Hard Right 389

ii Economic Discontents 399

iii Geopolitical Loneliness 410

iv Nationhood, Citizenship, and Identity 421

v Intellectual Doubts and Disaffection 439

15 The Primacy of Politics 454

Works Consulted 467

Name Index 495

Subject Index 507

What People are Saying About This

From the Publisher

"In this wonderfully fluent tour through the history of modern liberal thinking, Edmund Fawcett examines a generous selection of important thinkers from the 1830s to our own time in a way that locates both the lineage of their political thinking and the politics of their times. Sharp analysis is combined with a compelling narrative of serious thinkers at work. There is much to learn in this book, which is truly a joy to read. He makes judgments, but they are aids, not substitutes, for our own thinking about liberalism as an idea and about its present possibilities."—Thomas Bender, New York University

"Liberalism: The Life of an Idea possesses both the authority made possible by sustained scholarly research, and the clarity and simplicity found in first-rate journalism. It covers two centuries of the history of a principle guiding political practice and the various philosophies that have attempted to justify or defame it. It is a very timely reminder of the achievements and problems of a political tradition now everywhere under siege."—Gareth Stedman Jones, University of Cambridge and Queen Mary, University of London

"[A] fine work of intellectual history that shows, among much else, that experience can shape ideas, too."—William Anthony Hay

"Elegant, fluently written, and wryly amusing, this enlightening history of liberalism tells a persuasive story of ideas and politics through the lives of a huge variety of characters. The result is tremendously enjoyable."—Duncan Kelly, author of The Propriety of Liberty

"This is, quite simply, one of the most lively and engaging books that I've read in some time. With a brisk narrative that holds the reader's attention from start to finish, Liberalism provides a comprehensive survey of the subject, introducing a remarkable diversity of people and ideas, and offering a creative reconsideration of familiar tensions. It is impossible to imagine a reader who wouldn't learn much from it. I certainly did."—Ryan Patrick Hanley, author of Adam Smith and the Character of Virtue

"Not only a gripping piece of intellectual history, it also equips the reader to understand today's threats—and how they might be withstood…. Liberalism is indeed under siege. Those who would fortify the walls would do well to study the foundations…. Fawcett's book offers an admirable archaeology."The Economist

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews