Why We Vote: How Schools and Communities Shape Our Civic Life

Why We Vote: How Schools and Communities Shape Our Civic Life

by David E. Campbell
ISBN-10:
069113829X
ISBN-13:
9780691138299
Pub. Date:
08/10/2008
Publisher:
Princeton University Press
ISBN-10:
069113829X
ISBN-13:
9780691138299
Pub. Date:
08/10/2008
Publisher:
Princeton University Press
Why We Vote: How Schools and Communities Shape Our Civic Life

Why We Vote: How Schools and Communities Shape Our Civic Life

by David E. Campbell

Paperback

$37.0
Current price is , Original price is $37.0. You
$37.00 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores
  • SHIP THIS ITEM

    Temporarily Out of Stock Online

    Please check back later for updated availability.


Overview

Why do more people vote—or get involved in other civic and political activities—in some communities than in others? Why We Vote demonstrates that our communities shape our civic and political engagement, and that schools are especially significant communities for fostering strong civic norms.


Much of the research on political participation has found that levels of participation are higher in diverse communities where issues important to voters are hotly contested. In this well-argued book, David Campbell finds support for this view, but also shows that homogenous communities often have very high levels of civic participation despite a lack of political conflict.


Campbell maintains that this sense of civic duty springs not only from one's current social environment, but also from one's early influences. The degree to which people feel a sense of civic obligation stems, in part, from their adolescent experience. Being raised and thus socialized in a community with strong civic norms leads people to be civically engaged in adulthood. Campbell demonstrates how the civic norms within one's high school impact individuals' civic involvement—even a decade and a half after those individuals have graduated.


Efforts within America's high schools to enhance young people's sense of civic responsibility could have a participatory payoff in years to come, the book concludes; thus schools would do well to focus more attention on building civic norms among their students.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780691138299
Publisher: Princeton University Press
Publication date: 08/10/2008
Series: Princeton Studies in American Politics , #100
Edition description: New Edition
Pages: 280
Product dimensions: 6.10(w) x 9.20(h) x 0.60(d)

About the Author

David E. Campbell is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of Notre Dame. He is a coauthor of Democracy at Risk: How Political Choices Undermine Citizen Participation, and What We Can Do About It and The Education Gap: Vouchers and Urban Schools as well as a coeditor of Charters, Vouchers, and Public Education.

Read an Excerpt

Why We Vote How Schools and Communities Shape Our Civic Life


By David E. Campbell Princeton University Press
Copyright © 2006
Princeton University Press
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-13829-9


Chapter One INTRODUCTION: VOTING ALONE

On September 26, 1989, Traci Hodgson cast her ballot in Boston's City Council election. It was the only vote cast in her precinct. For a number of reasons, the political science literature predicts that Traci should have been like the other 275 registrants in her precinct and not turned out to vote. She was only twenty-one, she had lived in Boston for less than two months, and she admitted that she was "not very familiar with the candidates running." So why did she vote? When asked she replied, "I just think it's important to vote. If you have the right, you ought to exercise it-whether you are going to make a difference or not" (Mooney 1989).

This book is about why Traci voted, and why she voted alone.

MADISON AND TOCQUEVILLE: A TALE OF TWO MOTIVATIONS

Our starting point in answering this question is not what did motivate Traci, but rather what did not. Clearly she did not vote to protect or advance her interests, as she admitted that she did not know enough about the candidates to select them on the basis of who best represented her. To someone with only a cursory familiarity with the study of American politics this may seem difficult to explain, as politics is typically described as a forum for the "clash ofinterests." Equating politics with conflict underpins much of the political science literature and is an assumption shared by scholars working within many theoretical frameworks. I recall an introductory political science course in which a professor defined politics as the "scarcity of consensus." In 1960, E. E. Schattschneider wrote simply, "At the root of all politics is the universal language of conflict" (2). Forty years later, Morris Fiorina and Paul Peterson note matter-of-factly in their introductory textbook on American politics that "politics is fundamentally about conflict" (1998, xvi). For all the ink spilled by contemporary political scientists, however, no one has ever expressed this way of understanding politics better than James Madison in Federalist 10. Madison writes compellingly of how "the latent causes of faction are thus sown in the nature of man," and that "the most frivolous and fanciful distinctions have been sufficient to kindle their unfriendly passions and excite their most violent conflicts" (1961, 79).

It does not seem, however, that Traci had her passions kindled as Madison describes. Instead, by her own account she was motivated by the glowing embers of obligation. She felt that she ought to vote, that it was her duty.

In invoking a sense of duty as a motivation to vote, Traci highlights a second, if more subtle, theme in both contemporary and classic writings on political engagement. If, in Federalist 10, Madison has written the quintessential statement on political participation as "protecting one's interests," then perhaps Tocqueville has written an equally quintessential description of political participation as driven by "fulfilling one's duty." In Democracy in America, Tocqueville observes that American political institutions lead citizens to see that "it is the duty as well as the interest of men to be useful to their fellows.... What had been calculation becomes instinct. By dint of working for the good of his fellow citizens, he in the end acquires a habit and taste for serving them" (1988, 512-13).

These two opposing views of politics are not merely the abstract statements of theoreticians, the political science rendition of how many angels can dance on the head of a pin. They also inform the writings and doings of political practitioners, with some of America's founders as notable examples. Of course, Madison was one of the founders and, as noted, in his words we find a cogent description of how politics is inevitably defined by conflict. However, George Washington's vision was of a republic free from strife among its citizens, in which citizens were involved in public affairs out of duty (Schudson 1998). Ironically, given their disagreements on so many other matters, Thomas Jefferson's vision for the new republic mirrored Washington's. Jefferson idealized a nation of small Tocquevillian communities, mentioning his ideal in almost every speech he gave (Morone 1990).

The ongoing debate between civic republican and liberal political philosophers over the nature of political life at the time of America's founding underscores the two competing visions of democracy's nature. In summarizing this extensive literature, James Morone writes,

[T]he dominant interpretation of liberal America focuses on the pursuit of self-interest.... In the republican view, the colonial and Revolutionary ideal lay, not in the pursuit of private matters, but in the shared public life of civic duty, in the subordination of individual interests to the res publica. Citizens were defined and fulfilled by participation in political community. (1990, 16, emphasis added)

The distinction between engagement driven by interests versus duty need not be seen as either/or. The very fact that evidence can be mustered to support both interpretations of the founders' ideals suggests that neither one dominated to the exclusion of the other. Nor should we assume that the essential difference between engagement spurred by a threat to one's interests and engagement motivated by a sense of civic obligation has faded over time. Indeed, the distinction between interest-driven and duty-driven engagement is at the core of this book, which is about contemporary patterns of public engagement in the United States.

TRACI AND TOCQUEVILLE

While articulating that engagement in the public square is driven by Tocquevillian as well as Madisonian impulses underscores that there are two fundamentally different motivations for political activity, this observation alone does not provide much theoretical traction for empirical analysis. On its own, "fulfilling one's duty" remains at best a tautological explanation for political participation. It is far more interesting to ask why Traci felt that voting was her duty.

A potential answer to that question was intuitively included in the newspaper article that told of Traci's lonely ballot. Traci, the reader learns, had just moved to Boston from Kansas. She was born and raised in the town of Little River, population 693-a community that advertises itself as a "town with a lot of civic pride." Significantly, in 1992 voter turnout in Little River was 67 percent, 12 percentage points higher than turnout nationwide, and 27 points higher than in Boston. Armed with this information about Traci's hometown it seems plausible, even probable, that Traci voted because she hails from a community where voting is common. One might say that you can take the girl out of Kansas, but you can't take the Kansas out of the girl.

There has long been a strain of research in political science that examines the role of place in understanding political behavior, although with the dominance of survey research in this literature, far more attention has been paid to individuals' characteristics (King 1997). Loosely grouped together in a literature often labeled "contextual effects," a small but growing set of studies have examined how the characteristics of the communities in which people live affect their political activity. Decades ago, Paul Lazarsfeld and his Columbia School colleagues took voters' social environments seriously (Lazarsfeld, Berelson, and Gaudet 1948; Berelson, Lazarsfeld, and McPhee 1954), as have authors like Robert Huckfeldt and John Sprague (1995), Eric Oliver (2001), and James Gimpel, J. Celeste Lay, and Jason Schuknecht (2003) more recently.

The burgeoning literature on social capital has redirected political scientists' attention to important differences among geographic units, whether they be Italian regions, U.S. states, or nation-states. As Putnam explains in Making Democracy Work, social capital consists of "trust, norms, and networks" (1993, 167) that foster collective action. Putnam demonstrates that Italian states have deep, longstanding historical differences in the extent to which their residents engage in various forms of collective action. In Bowling Alone, he employs a multi-item index of social capital for each of the fifty states, which includes voter turnout (2000).

Viewed through the lens offered by the social capital literature, then, we might be tempted to attribute Traci's vote to her having lived in a place with a lot of social capital. The problem with this explanation is that it still provides little analytical leverage. Rather than "people vote because they feel they should," now the explanation is "people vote because they live in a place where voting is the norm." And how do we know that voting is the norm? Because many people vote there. This might be a small theoretical step forward, but not much more. The challenge is to find an explanation for why those norms are stronger in some places than in others.

The first section of this book deals precisely with just such an explanation. Presaging an argument that will be detailed further in chapters to come, I suggest that people vote out of both Madisonian and Tocquevillian motivations. In some communities more voters come to the polls in order to protect their interests, whereas in other places more of them cast a ballot because they feel it is their duty to do so. In these latter communities, civic norms are strong. Those norms are strong, in turn, because of consensus over values-what political scientists are more likely to call interests, and what economists call preferences. Where many people share the same values social norms are more easily enforced, specifically a norm encouraging civic participation. Diverse interests breed conflict, while uniformity fosters consensus; voter turnout can spring from both, but for different reasons. Furthermore, some forms of engagement in the community are more common in consensual communities, other forms in places better characterized as conflictual.

Assuming that I convince the reader that communities vary in the degree to which they can be characterized by their consensus over values, and thus in the extent to which their residents act in accordance with civic norms, Traci's vote will nonetheless remain unexplained. Remember that when she cast her ballot, Traci was not actually living in homogeneous Little River, Kansas, but heterogeneous Boston, Massachusetts. Why would Traci vote out of a sense of duty once she had moved away from a place with strong civic norms? Tocqueville hints at the answer when in the quotation above he refers to people acting out of duty because it had become their "instinct," having acquired a "habit and taste" for it. Traci had internalized the norm that voting is a duty and continued her duty-driven behavior even when she moved to a place where those norms would not be enforced. Critically, she spent her adolescence enmeshed in a community where civic norms were strong. During this particularly formative period of our lives, we are prone to developing habits that stay with us throughout our lives. In short, one can be socialized into acting out of a sense of duty, and an important (probably the most important) period of our lives for that socialization to occur is adolescence.

Again foreshadowing a more thorough discussion later, socialization is an important, if often implied, component of social capital theory. For example, while Putnam does not specifically raise the importance of childhood socialization in his discussion of civic traditions in Italy, it is certainly implied. How else would civic traditions perpetuate across time if the norms that constitute social capital were not transmitted across generations? Likewise, Putnam's more recent stress on differences in civic engagement among generational cohorts implies that members of different generations have, collectively, undergone distinctive socialization experiences.

Why did Traci vote? Because she was raised in a community where she internalized the norm that voting is her civic duty. The simplicity of this statement, however, belies the complexity of the theoretical foundation upon which it rests. Implicit within it are a number of claims, none of which is necessarily conventional wisdom within political science. To make the case that the communities in which we spend our adolescence affect whether we vote in adulthood first requires establishing that

a. communities shape the civic and political engagement of the people who live within them, or what you do now depends on where you are now b. the engagement of adolescents in particular is shaped by where they live, or what you did then depends on where you were then c. adolescents' engagement links to their engagement as adults, or what you do now depends on what you did then

Together these claims lay the foundation for the book's central argument: the civic norms within one's adolescent social environment have an effect on civic participation well beyond adolescence: what you do now depends on where you were then. These points all require theoretical justification and empirical evaluation, and so a section of the book is devoted to each.

WHAT YOU DO NOW DEPENDS ON WHERE YOU ARE NOW

Chapters 2-4 demonstrate that the communities in which we live shape the nature of what I will refer to as our public engagement. I use this particular term to describe what other authors generally call, interchangeably, civic or political engagement. I do this because I draw a distinction between engagement which is civic and that which is political. We will get into more formal definitions in chapter 2, but for now an intuitive example provides a sense of what I see as the critical difference between the two. Imagine that someone wanted to help the homeless population in her community. One way would be to volunteer at a soup kitchen that serves the homeless, an example of what I mean by civic, or civically motivated, engagement. Another way would be to volunteer for a candidate who has promised to enact policies to assist the homeless, or to march at the state capitol in support of a bill designed to address their needs. This second type of activity is what I define as engagement with a political motivation. Both types of engagement are public, in the sense that they have an effect beyond oneself and the people in one's immediate sphere of influence. The fundamental distinction between them is not their ends-in both cases, the intention is to assist the homeless-but rather their means. Political participation has as its immediate objective to affect public policy, while its civic counterpart does not.

In places characterized by conflict, politically motivated public engagement is more common. Conversely, communities where there is relative consensus are more likely to host civic engagement, because these communities have strong civic norms encouraging engagement in publicly spirited activities. This, in a nutshell, is what I have labeled the dual motivations theory of public engagement. Chapter 2 applies the theory to voter turnout, one form of engagement that shares both motivations. Contrary to a strictly Madisonian perspective on politics, voter turnout rises where there is a relative absence of political conflict-where elections are blowouts-because voting has civic, as well as political, underpinnings. Madison, however, is redeemed by the observation that turnout also rises in communities where there is a high degree of political conflict. Chapter 3 then turns its attention to other evidence in support of the dual motivations theory. First, we see that voters are more likely to report voting out of a sense of duty in politically consensual communities, and more likely to vote to accomplish policy objectives in places with a high degree of conflict. Similarly, engagement on the civic side of the spectrum is more likely in consensual than conflictual communities, while politically motivated activity is more common in places known for conflict. Chapter 4 continues to test implications of the dual motivations theory, in this case by changing the focus of the inquiry from large-scale communities like cities and counties to personal social networks. Living in a homogeneous community makes it more likely that someone will have a homogeneous social network, which in turn spurs civically motivated public engagement.

(Continues...)



Excerpted from Why We Vote by David E. Campbell
Copyright © 2006 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

List of Figures ix

List of Tables xi

Acknowledgments xiii

Chapter One: Introduction: Voting Alone 1

Part One: What You Do Now Depends on Where You Are Now 11

Chapter Two: Putting Madison and Tocqueville to the Test: The Dual Motivations Theory of Public Engagement 13

Chapter Three: Further Implications of the Dual Motivations Theory 50

Chapter Four: Social Networks 76

Part Two: What You Did Then Depends on Where You Were Then 93

Chapter Five: Social Environments and Adolescents' Public Engagement 95

Part Three: What You Do Now Depends on What You Did Then 129

Chapter Six: The Links between Adolescents' and Adults' Public Engagement 131

Part Four: What You Do Now Depends on Where You Were Then 145

Chapter Seven: Adolescents' Social Environments and Adults' Public Engagement: The Civic Motivation Model 147

Chapter Eight: Conclusion: Implications for Theory and Policy 180

Appendix A: Data Sources 201

Appendix B: Questions from the 1996 National Election Study Used in Table 2.1 and Figure 2.4 204

Appendix C: Full Results of Models Discussed in the Text 208

Notes 223

Bibliography 243

Index 261

What People are Saying About This

Richard Niemi

This book provides the first solid, generalizable evidence of the influence of an adolescent's surroundings on adult political behavior. It offers a significant contribution to the study of voter turnout by showing how citizen duty is a factor in predicting political participation.
Richard Niemi, University of Rochester

From the Publisher

"This book provides the first solid, generalizable evidence of the influence of an adolescent's surroundings on adult political behavior. It offers a significant contribution to the study of voter turnout by showing how citizen duty is a factor in predicting political participation."—Richard Niemi, University of Rochester

"Why We Vote makes an important contribution to our understanding of the ways community contexts prompt voting. This clear and compelling analysis will add energy to the resurgence of interest in the study of political socialization."—Joseph Kahne, Mills College

Joseph Kahne

Why We Vote makes an important contribution to our understanding of the ways community contexts prompt voting. This clear and compelling analysis will add energy to the resurgence of interest in the study of political socialization.
Joseph Kahne, Mills College

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews