Spatial Models of Parliamentary Voting

Spatial Models of Parliamentary Voting

by Keith T. Poole
ISBN-10:
0521617472
ISBN-13:
9780521617475
Pub. Date:
04/11/2005
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
ISBN-10:
0521617472
ISBN-13:
9780521617475
Pub. Date:
04/11/2005
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Spatial Models of Parliamentary Voting

Spatial Models of Parliamentary Voting

by Keith T. Poole
$40.99 Current price is , Original price is $40.99. You
$40.99 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores
  • SHIP THIS ITEM

    Temporarily Out of Stock Online

    Please check back later for updated availability.


Overview

This book presents a geometric voting model for analyzing parliamentary roll call data. Each legislator is represented by one point and each roll call is represented by two points that correspond to the policy consequences of voting Yea or Nay. On every roll call each legislator votes for the closer outcome point, at least probabilistically. These points form a spatial map that summarizes the roll calls. In this sense a spatial map is much like a road map because it visually depicts the political world of a legislature. These maps can be used to study a wide variety of topics related to legislative voting.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780521617475
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Publication date: 04/11/2005
Series: Analytical Methods for Social Research
Edition description: New Edition
Pages: 248
Product dimensions: 5.98(w) x 8.98(h) x 0.75(d)

About the Author

Keith T. Poole is a Professor of Political Science at the University of California, San Diego. He is the author or coauthor of over 40 articles as well as the coauthor of Congress: A Political-Economic History of Roll Call Voting and Income Redistribution and the Realignment of American Politics.

Read an Excerpt

Spatial Models of Parliamentary Voting
Cambridge University Press
0521851947 - Spatial Models of Parliamentary Voting - by Keith T. Poole
Excerpt



CHAPTER 1

Introduction


Overview

In this book I show how to use a simple spatial model of voting as a tool to analyze parliamentary roll call data. Each legislator is represented by one point, and each roll call is represented by two points - one for Yea and one for Nay. On every roll call each legislator votes for the closer outcome point, at least probabilistically. These points form a spatial map that summarizes the roll calls. In this sense a spatial map is much like a road map. A spreadsheet that tabulates all the distances between pairs of sizable cities in the U.S. contains the same information as the corresponding map of the U.S., but the spreadsheet gives you no idea what the U.S. looks like.1 Much like a road map, a spatial map formed from roll calls gives us a way of visualizing the political world of a legislature. The closeness of two legislators on the map shows how similar their voting records are, and the distribution of legislators shows what the dimensions of the space are.

The number of dimensions needed to represent the points is usually small, because legislators typically decide how to vote on the basis of their positions on a small number of underlying evaluative, or basic, dimensions. For example, in recent U.S. Congresses, we can easily predict how a "liberal" or a "conservative" will vote on most issues. These basic dimensions structure the roll call votes and are captured by the spatial maps.

In this chapter I develop a simple theory of spatial maps that I call the basic-space theory of ideology. In subsequent chapters I use the theory to show how to construct and interpret the spatial maps that reflect it. The theory is based on the work of many scholars in psychology, economics, and political science over the past 50 years and is a parsimonious tool for understanding the construction and interpretation of spatial maps.

I begin with some observations on theory and meaning. A spatial map is a picture, and for it to be a summary, it must have a meaning for the viewer. That meaning must flow from a theory about the picture. In this sense, "a picture is worth a thousand words." My point is simple. Anyone can construct a spatial map using the computer programs I discuss in subsequent chapters. But the maps are worthless unless the user understands both the spatial theory that the computer program embodies and the politics of the legislature that produced the roll calls. A practitioner must be able to stand before an audience of her peers and explain the meaning of the spatial map.

After discussing theory and meaning, the rest of the chapter lays out my theory of spatial maps.

Theory and Meaning

To reiterate, this is a book about the use of pictures to summarize parliamentary roll call data. For the most part these pictures consist of simple geometric representations of the legislators and of the roll calls. For example, members of the left, or liberal, party cluster together on one side of the picture, and members of the right, or conservative, party cluster together on the opposite side of the picture. In this case a glance at the picture by an experienced researcher shows what the main sources of conflict are within the parliament and how the roll call voting is structured. By "experienced" I mean that the researcher must understand how the picture was constructed and must understand the political environment of the parliament or legislature. It is the researcher's understanding of the theory about the picture that gives the picture meaning. Without this understanding a person viewing the picture would see just a bunch of dots (or tokens; see Figure 1.2). This would be like someone not trained in physics trying to make sense out of cloud chamber photographs, or someone not trained in electronics trying to make sense out of an ammeter reading of a plate current, and so on.2

Image not available in HTML version

FIGURE 1.1. Mona Lisa.

Although the pictures that are the subject of this book - spatial maps of parliamentary voting - are not art, the concept of picture-as-summary is a slippery one that must be used with caution. The boundary line between picture-as-summary and picture-as-art is not as clear as it may appear. For example, consider the most recognized picture in the world - Leonardo da Vinci's painting, Mona Lisa (Figure 1.1).3 Why does this painting seem to transcend cultures and national boundaries? Is it the finest portrait ever painted? Is it more important than Picasso's Les Demoiselles d'Avignon?4 The answer of course is obvious - the smile. But why the smile? In my opinion Leonardo's genius was, figuratively, to flip a coin and have it land on its edge. He managed to paint a facial expression that is exactly on the cusp between a smile and a frown. Consequently, when we look at the painting, it does not instantly match what we recognize as a smile or a frown. So we attend to it longer than we normally would, and we have to think about it. Hence our fascination.

Not everyone will agree with my interpretation5 of Mona Lisa, but consensus is not my purpose in offering it. Clearly, Mona Lisa is not a picture-as-summary for most people. Most people see a beautiful painting of a woman with an ambiguous smile. I see a perceptual trick much like the simple figures used by the Gestalt psychologists. It is high art and the work of a great scientific mind. This meaning of the picture for me flows from my theory of the picture.

A Theory of Spatial Maps

Unlike my Mona Lisa theory, the basic space theory of ideology underlying the spatial maps of parliamentary voting analyzed in this book is the end result of the work of a large number of scholars. I am deliberately using the word "theory" broadly and loosely for now. In the notion of theory I include: (1) the technical apparatus of the spatial model; (2) a theory of how legislators make decisions; (3) a theory of belief systems (ideology) that is tied to the assumptions of the spatial model and the theory of decision-making; (4) the computer program that embodies (1), (2), and (3) and actually generates the spatial maps; and (5) a substantive understanding of the political system that the parliament or legislature is embedded in. All these are necessary for meaning to flow from the spatial map. Simply pushing a matrix of roll call data through a computer program does not itself produce a meaningful picture.

For example, Figure 1.2 is a spatial map of the final passage vote of the landmark 1964 Civil Rights Act in the U.S. Senate.6 The act was one of the most important roll call votes in U.S. history. It was passed seven months after President John Kennedy was assassinated in November of 1963. In June of 1963 Kennedy introduced his civil rights bill to the nation in a nationally televised address. In a supreme act of leadership, he argued that it was a moral issue

Image not available in HTML version

FIGURE 1.2. Final passage vote on the 1964 Civil Rights Act. Each token corresponds to a senator's ideal point. R stands for Republican, D for Northern Democrat, and S for Southern Democrat. Errors are concentrated near the cutting line. The ideal points and the cutting line are estimates from the DW-NOMINATE model, with a linear time trend in legislator positions. The second dimension is shown unweighted for purposes of clarity.

that went to the heart of how people treated one another. Discrimination on the basis of skin color was morally wrong, and it must be ended.7 President Lyndon Johnson in his January 1964 State of the Union address made the civil rights legislation introduced by Kennedy his top legislative priority, and he pushed it through Congress with the help of the Republican and Northern Democratic Congressional leaders.8

The spatial map is from DW-NOMINATE (McCarty, Poole, and Rosenthal, 1997; Poole and Rosenthal, 2001). The left panel shows all the senators, and the right panel shows just the five senators who were errors in the DW-NOMINATE analysis.9 Each senator's location in the map is a function of all the roll calls the senator participated in during his/her career. The cutting line is specific to the roll call and divides the senators who are predicted to vote Yea from those who are predicted to vote Nay. The senators who are predicted incorrectly are errors.

Consider just the spatial map of all the senators. The descriptive labels and the relative positions of the party tokens in the map show that a coalition of Republicans and Northern Democrats voted for the act and a coalition of Southern10 Democrats and a few Republicans voted against the act.11 The map also shows a clear separation of the Democrats from the Republicans and a sharp division within the Democratic Party. All but four of the Southern Democrats are up near the top of the map.

My analysis of Figure 1.2 so far has not revealed any information that a sophisticated student of American political history would not already know. For me to go any further requires that I say something about the structure of the map. I have to explain what the dimensions represent and explain the relative placement of the D, S, and R tokens on the dimensions. These explanations of the structure of the map cannot be based on the technical apparatus that produced the map. Rather, they must be grounded in the substance of American politics. Furthermore, I have to assume that the reader believes that the technical apparatus that produced the map is reliable and that the reader has a basic understanding of it. Consequently, for me to go further and offer my interpretation of the spatial map of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, I need to outline my theory of spatial maps.

Spatial Models of Voting

The spatial maps used in this book rest on the work of researchers in psychology, economics, and political science. The three fields are equally important to the theory.

In psychology various methods of multidimensional scaling (MDS) have been developed during the past 50 years to analyze similarity and preferential choice data. For example, a set of respondents are asked to judge how similar various countries are to each other. MDS methods model these similarities as distances between points representing the countries in a geometric space. These MDS programs are designed to produce a picture-as-summary - literally to summarize a large set of data graphically.12

At the same time psychologists were developing MDS, economists and political scientists were developing the spatial theory of voting. In its simplest form the spatial theory of voting can be represented as a map of voters and candidates where the voters vote for the candidate closest to them. In this regard, a spatial map is literally a visual representation of the spatial model of voting. Although Hotelling (1929) and Smithies (1941) are credited with originating the idea, it was the publication of Anthony Downs's An Economic Theory of Democracy in 1957 that really established spatial theory as a conceptual tool.

Hotelling studied the logic of the location of a grocery store in a linear town - that is, a town strung out along a highway, where all the houses face a single road. It is easy to demonstrate that the optimum location for a grocery store is the median of the town (the median minimizes the sum of the walking distances to the store). Hotelling showed that if there are two grocery stores, they will locate adjacent to one another. Smithies elaborated this model a bit by introducing elastic demand, so that people at the edges of town might stop shopping at the store if it moved too far to the center (Downs, 1957, p. 117). Hence the stores might not converge at the median of the town.

Downs took the Hotelling-Smithies model of spatial competition of stores and applied it to the competition of political parties. He assumed that voters were distributed over a dimension - for example, government intervention in the economy - and that political parties played the role of the stores. He derived a large number of classic results from this simple model. For example, if voters vote for the party closest to them on the dimension, the parties will converge to the median voter. Duncan Black (1948, 1958) had earlier derived a similar result for voting in committees.

Although Downs's work is a brilliant tour de force, it did not present spatial theory in a form that was susceptible to empirical testing. No rigorous mathematical structure was presented from which measuring instruments could be designed to test the theory. The needed structure was provided by the work of Otto Davis, Melvin Hinich, and Peter Ordeshook (Davis and Hinich, 1966; Davis, Hinich, and Ordeshook, 1970). By the early 1970s the mathematical structure of spatial theory was largely completed. The dimensions of the space represented issues or policies. Each voter had a position on each issue or policy, and this vector of positions was the voter's ideal point in the space. Each voter also had a utility function centered on her ideal point that assigned a utility to each point in the space. The further a point was from the voter's ideal point, the lower the utility. Each candidate also had a position on each issue dimension and therefore was represented as a point in the space. Each voter then voted for the candidate for whom she had the highest utility. In the context of parliamentary voting, the model is exactly the same, only policy outcomes rather than candidates for public office are now the choices.

This early version of the spatial theory of voting did not allow for error by voters. That is, voting was deterministic. Voters had ideal points and voted for the candidate closest to them in the policy space. Later, more realistic assumptions about voters' decision rules allowed for probabilistic voting.13 Nevertheless, this version of spatial theory could at least be investigated empirically.

Psychometrics and Tests of Spatial Theory

In order to test the spatial theory of voting, you need data from voters about how "far" they are from candidates. The first comprehensive test of spatial theory was by Cahoon (1975) and Cahoon, Hinich, and Ordeshook (1976; 1978) using candidate feeling thermometers. Beginning in 1968, feeling thermometers were included in the NES surveys. A feeling thermometer measures how warm or cold a person feels toward the stimulus; the measure ranges from 0 (very cold, unfavorable feeling) to 100 (very warm, favorable feeling), with 50 as a neutral point. In 1968 respondents were asked to give feeling thermometer ratings to the presidential candidates George Wallace, Hubert Humphrey, and Richard Nixon, along with their vice presidential running mates and six other political figures.14 These thermometer scores can be interpreted as distances between the respondent's ideal point and the spatial positions of the candidates. For example, if a respondent gave Humphrey a 100, Nixon a 40, and Wallace a 0, then she was likely to be very close to Humphrey, very far from Wallace, but closer to Nixon than to Wallace.

Cahoon constructed a statistical model of the thermometer scores based on the spatial theory of voting and found that a simple two-dimensional spatial map largely accounted for the observed thermometer scores. His predictions of how the respondents would vote closely matched their actual voting choices.

Figure 1.3 shows a configuration of presidential candidates similar to that estimated by Cahoon. The horizontal dimension is from liberal (on the left) to conservative (on the right), and the vertical dimension is from Democratic (toward the top) to Republican (toward the bottom).

Cahoon was the first to test the spatial theory of voting using thermometer scores, but he was not the first to construct spatial maps from thermometer scores. Herbert Weisberg and Jerrold Rusk (1970) used the MDS procedure developed by Kruskal (1964a,b) to recover a candidate configuration from the candidate-by-candidate correlation matrix computed across the respondents. They did not estimate the respondents' locations.15

Although the spatial maps produced by Cahoon and by Weisberg and Rusk are essentially the same and are both pictures-as-summary, they have very different theoretical foundations. The MDS procedures developed by psychologists were intended to help answer questions of importance to psychologists. Namely, given a set of judged similarities between objects (nations, colors, types of crime, emotional states, etc.), researchers could use MDS procedures to uncover underlying psychological dimensions or as a tool to formulate a convincing description of the data. For example, two dimensions - communist-noncommunist and developed-underdeveloped - were found to underlie similarity judgments of nations (Kruskal and Wish, 1978). In contrast, the spatial theory of voting is a theory of behavior that states that if a set of assumptions holds, then voters should behave in a certain way and we should observe certain types of outcomes. It is a theory that makes predictions that can be tested.

Image not available in HTML version

FIGURE 1.3. Spatial map of the 1968 presidential candidates. The map was produced by applying nonmetric multidimensional scaling to the candidate-by-candidate Pearson correlation matrix computed from the feeling thermometers.

Although the theoretical foundations are different, as a practical matter the MDS procedures developed by the psychologists are very similar in form to procedures developed to test spatial theory. A full-blown test of spatial theory like that performed by Cahoon estimates ideal points for the voters and points for the candidates in a spatial map such that the distances between the voters and candidates in the map are as close as possible to the original data. For example, the thermometers range from 0 to 100. Cahoon transformed these into distances by subtracting the thermometer value from 100. Finding points for the voters and points for the candidates that reproduce these distances is known as an unfolding analysis in psychology (Coombs, 1964). Techniques to perform unfolding analyses were developed by psychologists in the 1950s and 1960s (Chang and Carroll, 1969; Kruskal, Young, and Seery, 1973), and Cahoon's is also an unfolding methodology. Later Rabinowitz (1976), Poole and Rosenthal (1984a), and Brady (1990) developed unfolding procedures that they applied to thermometer scores.16



© Cambridge University Press

Table of Contents

1. Introduction; 2. The geometry of parliamentary roll call voting; 3. The optimal classification method; 4. Probabilistic spatial models of parliamentary voting; 5. Practical issues in computing spatial models of parliamentary voting; 6. Conducting natural experiments with role calls; 7. Conclusion.
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews