Systems We Have Loved: Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn
By the early 1960s, theorists like Lévi-Strauss, Lacan, Foucault, and Barthes had created a world ruled by signifying structures and pictured through the grids of language, information, and systems. Artists soon followed, turning to language and its related forms to devise a new, conceptual approach to art making. Examining the ways in which artists shared the structuralist devotion to systems of many sorts, Systems We Have Loved shows that even as structuralism encouraged the advent of conceptual art, it also raised intractable problems that artists were forced to confront.   Considering such notable art figures as Mary Kelly, Robert Morris, Robert Smithson, and Rosalind Krauss, Eve Meltzer argues that during this period the visual arts depicted and tested the far-reaching claims about subjectivity espoused by theorists. She offers a new way of framing two of the twentieth century’s most transformative movements—one artistic, one expansively theoretical—and she reveals their shared dream—or nightmare—of the world as a system of signs. By endorsing this view, Meltzer proposes, these artists drew attention to the fictions and limitations of this dream, even as they risked getting caught in the very systems they had adopted. The first book to describe art’s embrace of the world as an information system, Systems We Have Loved breathes new life into the study of conceptual art.
1112822527
Systems We Have Loved: Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn
By the early 1960s, theorists like Lévi-Strauss, Lacan, Foucault, and Barthes had created a world ruled by signifying structures and pictured through the grids of language, information, and systems. Artists soon followed, turning to language and its related forms to devise a new, conceptual approach to art making. Examining the ways in which artists shared the structuralist devotion to systems of many sorts, Systems We Have Loved shows that even as structuralism encouraged the advent of conceptual art, it also raised intractable problems that artists were forced to confront.   Considering such notable art figures as Mary Kelly, Robert Morris, Robert Smithson, and Rosalind Krauss, Eve Meltzer argues that during this period the visual arts depicted and tested the far-reaching claims about subjectivity espoused by theorists. She offers a new way of framing two of the twentieth century’s most transformative movements—one artistic, one expansively theoretical—and she reveals their shared dream—or nightmare—of the world as a system of signs. By endorsing this view, Meltzer proposes, these artists drew attention to the fictions and limitations of this dream, even as they risked getting caught in the very systems they had adopted. The first book to describe art’s embrace of the world as an information system, Systems We Have Loved breathes new life into the study of conceptual art.
51.99 In Stock
Systems We Have Loved: Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn

Systems We Have Loved: Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn

by Eve Meltzer
Systems We Have Loved: Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn

Systems We Have Loved: Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn

by Eve Meltzer

eBook

$51.99 

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

By the early 1960s, theorists like Lévi-Strauss, Lacan, Foucault, and Barthes had created a world ruled by signifying structures and pictured through the grids of language, information, and systems. Artists soon followed, turning to language and its related forms to devise a new, conceptual approach to art making. Examining the ways in which artists shared the structuralist devotion to systems of many sorts, Systems We Have Loved shows that even as structuralism encouraged the advent of conceptual art, it also raised intractable problems that artists were forced to confront.   Considering such notable art figures as Mary Kelly, Robert Morris, Robert Smithson, and Rosalind Krauss, Eve Meltzer argues that during this period the visual arts depicted and tested the far-reaching claims about subjectivity espoused by theorists. She offers a new way of framing two of the twentieth century’s most transformative movements—one artistic, one expansively theoretical—and she reveals their shared dream—or nightmare—of the world as a system of signs. By endorsing this view, Meltzer proposes, these artists drew attention to the fictions and limitations of this dream, even as they risked getting caught in the very systems they had adopted. The first book to describe art’s embrace of the world as an information system, Systems We Have Loved breathes new life into the study of conceptual art.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780226007915
Publisher: University of Chicago Press
Publication date: 07/02/2013
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 240
File size: 47 MB
Note: This product may take a few minutes to download.

About the Author

Eve Meltzer is assistant professor of visual studies and visual culture in the Gallatin School of Individualized Study at New York University.

Read an Excerpt

Systems We Have Loved

Conceptual Art, Affect, and the Antihumanist Turn


By Eve Meltzer

THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS

Copyright © 2013 The University of Chicago
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-226-00788-5


CHAPTER 1

The Dream of the Information World


The world is really going to hell in a toboggan, and I'm putting these boxes together. ... But, you know, that's not the point. The point is ... [that the idea is] followed absolutely to its conclusion, which is mechanistic. It has no validity as anything except a process in itself. It has nothing to do with the world at all. —Sol LeWitt (1969)


Look at a print of a drawing produced by Sol LeWitt in 1967, and then used as the announcement for an exhibition of his work at the Dwan Gallery in Los Angeles that year (fig. 1.1). The drawing is a plan for four sets of nine pieces. One of these sets LeWitt has described graphically in both gridded form and written language. Take a grid, subdivide it into nine smaller, equivalent grids, then mark off each as its own isolated "piece." LeWitt has done just this, and then he has numbered the pieces from one to nine—a designation that appears to be their only distinguishing mark. Otherwise, these pieces appear to be completely identical, having been produced by the grid's fail-safe system of equivalences.

But look more closely and you'll see that LeWitt's drawing is actually asking us to imagine these nine pieces as distinct—he indicates this with a list of measurements jotted at the foot of the print. In fact, this set of nine pieces is more like Serial Project #1 (ABCD) from 1966–68 than the grid diagram would have us think (fig. 1.2). Each piece in the print is defined by the uniqueness of its variation. Like Serial Project, the print represents a field of cubic forms that rise to incremental heights, in the way an urban landscape or miniature architectural model appears from above. But the drawn set would be better described not as architectural or even inhabitable, but as structural. In fact, the artist prefers the term "structure," to the more usual one, "sculpture."

By 1967, the year LeWitt created this particular structure, the rules of structural order were widely and readily applied to nearly every field of cultural inquiry—mathematics, the empirical sciences, the social sciences, especially anthropology and psychology, and of course linguistics. In fact, by that year practitioners from a wide range of fields were calling upon the laws of structural order to examine and explain an extraordinarily vast range of cultural phenomena. In 1968 Jean Piaget, among many others, sought to define what exactly a structure is. In his terms, a structure is "not a mere collection of elements and their properties," but rather it "involve[s] laws: the structure is preserved or enriched by the interplay of its transformation laws, which never yield results external to the system nor employ elements that are external to it." The kind of structure I see LeWitt employing accords with Piaget's definition; it is a system of transformations. Looking closely at LeWitt's set of nine pieces, we can grasp that his grid's law of equivalences is actually used to spawn differences. There are only differences in LeWitt's structure. The meaning of each piece is not immanent in it, much in the same way that structuralist linguistics teaches us that the letters that form the word "cat" have no intrinsic meaning; they mean because they are not "cap" or "cad" or "bat." Furthermore, both field and module in LeWitt's structure are organized in such a way that precludes breaking the system, for the elements of any structure are always subordinate to its laws. Piaget explains that the elements "do not exist in isolation from one another, nor were they discovered one by one in some accidental sequence and then, finally, united into a whole. They do not come upon the scene except as ordered." We could say, therefore, that LeWitt's structure is predicated on the obdurate incontestability of the peculiar temporality of its order—always-already present as whole, like a grid whose elements come into being together and all at once, in an extraordinarily democratic way, in the very moment that the horizontal-vertical pattern is laid down. Moreover, to consider any one piece from LeWitt's set will always be an activity inextricable from the conceptual integrity of the whole.

Be sure to notice, as well, that LeWitt's grids do not actually operate for the work of art like a framework, as in the case of a picture rendered in one-point perspective; the grid structure does not function, as Lawrence Alloway has put it, "as the invisible servicing of the work of art." Rather, the grid structure is, as Alloway says, the "visible skin" of the work. He adds, emphatically, "it is not ... an underlying composition, but a factual display." And so if LeWitt's structure pictures a world—as I want to suggest it does—it does not do so in the way that we ordinarily associate with pictures. His grid does not serve as the armature for a scene represented, or for a ground with or without figures upon it. In fact, if LeWitt's structure could be said to indicate anything at all, it would be the very assurance that everything has been brought to the surface, or better, that the relationship between surface and depth, disclosure and hiddenness, visibility and invisibility, has been extinguished. LeWitt's grid declares that "everything is here." And it does so with a self-generated sense of autonomy, like a miniature world created ex nihilo. Even if we can't actually see it, everything is accounted for by the structural system, everything has been subsumed into its order of equivalences. Everything has been brought into absolute visibility, only now visibility is not a property of looking or even of the visual, but a figure of epistemic mastery.

This reconfiguration of the visible is critical here, not just for the self-definition of so-called conceptual art, but, more importantly, for the worldview out of which LeWitt's grid and so many other works of art like it grew. LeWitt's grid renounces the visual and, in its place, proposes that there is a deeper, structural logic governing its form that cannot, nor even need, be seen with our eyes. In 1967, just one year after the year most often cited as the start date for conceptual art, LeWitt turned this sort of practice into something of a mantra: "What the work of art looks like isn't too important." His language seems straightforward; he explains that, on the one hand, there is an art of the mind and, on the other, an art of the eye. LeWitt was not alone in making statements such as this; his words may stand in here for those of dozens of practitioners who might have said the same: Lawrence Weiner, Joseph Kosuth, and Douglas Huebler come first to my mind. "Art is not necessarily a visual experience," Huebler proclaimed two years later. "Art [is] the thing that comes into your head—and not ... a visual thing. You see, by using the visual thing and then suspending it, then the art has to be located in the idea and away from the visual appearance, you see." For Huebler, even seeing is not a thing of vision, but a figure of speech for grasping the concept. Indeed, LeWitt reiterated his disavowal of the visual within this very print. "These pieces should be made without regard for their appearance," he scrawled alongside the grid plan—as if to announce, along with the opening of his show at the Dwan Gallery, that we won't find what we're looking for by looking. Appearances should be disregarded.

Above all, it is the look of LeWitt's print that nearly causes us to overlook the obscurities of his language and swallow whole his stated disavowal of the visual. On first glance, it seems there is nothing to look at in the work; it is too lean, too stripped, too "pre-fact[ual]," to use his word—always before something else that never fully arrives. Or perhaps it is because when one looks, as Donald Kuspit has surmised, "one does not so much see [the work] as think about [it], in part because the seeing ... is quickly and fastidiously done." And when we do look, we quickly come up against the challenges of description. "It's like getting words caught in your eyes," wrote Robert Smithson after laying his eyes on this print.

But what if we asked—in spite of LeWitt's derogation of the visual, in the face of language's recalcitrance to being looked at, over and against the elusive transparency of the grid—what does the print look like? If we are to see this print as a species of the visual and understand the world that its aesthetic pictures, then we will have to read its structure with an eye to form, as one reads a dream. We will have to attend to the strategies of withholding that have shaped that which is, despite all claims to the contrary, certainly given to be seen.

To show how the visual matters to this work and so many others like it, I will advance three claims, each describing what LeWitt's print "looks like." Then, by way of an examination of the Information show, held at New York's Museum of Modern Art in 1970, I will elaborate the depth of their significance and explain what each has to do with the others. My first claim: LeWitt's Untitled looks like information. This is not just because the drawing informs us of the rules and specifications for the nine pieces, but also because the print has the look of information—to rethink Kuspit's figuration "the look of thought." As I will elaborate shortly, this "look of information" permits us to understand the technological imaginary of its historical moment.

My second claim will come as no surprise to readers of conceptual art: this drawing also looks like language. This is not merely because the drawing is largely composed of written form, but also because it has the look of language. To understand this idea, we will need to consider carefully the structuralist imaginary of this historical moment—the range of cultural forms language was said to represent and encompass, and the ways in which it was understood to perform that representation. And lastly, my third claim: LeWitt's Untitled print also looks like a work of art in a time of crisis, at least a late twentieth-century rendition. "The world is really going to hell in a toboggan," the artist said in a 1969 interview with Patricia Norvell, "and I'm putting these boxes together.... But, you know," he continues, "the point is [that the idea is] followed absolutely to its conclusion, which is mechanistic. It has no validity as anything except a process in itself. It has," he concludes, "nothing to do with the world at all." This look, I will explain, has everything to do with the world: not just contemporary events, movements, and catastrophes, of which there were so many at this time, but also the way in which we conceive of the world—not if it exists, for that would be to return to the inquiry of Descartes's "Meditation VI," in which the existence of the world is predicated on its presence to his faculty of knowledge alone, as he says, "the power and inward vision of my mind." LeWitt's print matters to the world with regard to the questioning of—as the phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty frames it—"what it is for [the world] to exist."

"Information," "language," and "the world" are far from self-evident terms. In fact, we have to read each as a piece of a much larger and more complex fantasmatic field. This is crucial if we are ever to understand truly what this visually confounding idiom was trying to say and why it erupted in the form of the visual in the first place. These terms are critical not just for understanding a single print by Sol LeWitt, but also for coming to terms with American art practice of the 1960s and '70s, when the linguistic forms and structural systems that appear in the print became a common lexicon often hitched to the word "information." That word we have come to associate more closely with the turn of the twenty-first century than with the 1960s and '70s. "Information" would seem to have more to do with present-day new media practices than with the comparatively clunky conceptualist aesthetic; it would seem to be more at issue with respect to our currently expanding technologies of communication, the Internet, bio-informatics, even information warfare and the U.S. Defense Department's originally named Total Information Awareness program, designed to mine databases for information to aid in the identification of terrorists. Indeed, the "informational" aesthetic prevalent around 1970 anticipates our present day. Here my primary aim is to explain how this aesthetic permits us to understand the broader cultural imaginary of the period surrounding the year 1970, its relationship to fantasies about contemporary technologies of communication and the politics that grew up with such fantasies. We know that the aims of these artistic practitioners were aesthetic and political. They embraced the critique of institutionalism, the reformulation of the relationship between art and audience, and the radical democratization of artistic production and consumption. That much many scholars have already made clear. But the deeper structure of the ideas and stakes with which artists were profoundly engaged—this, too, has been overlooked.

For even a work of art with an extreme economy of visual means is not the same as "not ... a visual thing," to recall Huebler's phrasing. Even a total negation of visibility still counts for the visible world. Take, for instance, Robert Barry's 1969 series of announcements stating that for the duration of the exhibition the gallery would be closed (fig. 1.3). Or consider Adrian Piper's Withdrawal Statement (1970), which replaced the work of art she withdrew from the Conceptual Art and Conceptual Aspects exhibition at the New York Cultural Center:

The work originally intended for this space has been withdrawn. The decision to withdraw has been taken as a protective measure against the increasingly pervasive conditions of fear. Rather than submit the work tothe deadly and poisoning influence of these conditions, I submit its absence as evidence of the inability of art expression to have meaningful existence under conditions other than those of peace, equality, truth, trust and freedom.


Both Barry and Piper represent a widespread belief in the aesthetic and political capacities of invisibility, withholding, and withdrawal as artistic strategies. Yet for all the economizing, negating, and conceptualizing that they and their contemporaries performed over the years, I want to claim that those strategies are, paradoxical though it may seem, the very means by which the artwork permits us to see what we otherwise could not. Abbreviated, stripped, informational, structural—what the work of art under these conditions shows us is that within the broader cultural imaginary the seemingly disparate discursive fields of "language" and "information" had become closely linked—condensed, combined, intertwined, quite like two otherwise unrelated terms might appear together as one in a dream. This is a dream of a world: a representation of what is before that and, at once, within which we find ourselves. And it is a dream that for nearly fifty years now has been normative and binding for us.

This dream, and the wish that motivated it, is the subject of this chapter.


Information, 1970

In an exhibition review, the critic Gregory Battcock conjures the Information show as a series of contradictory propositions:

Imagine: 1. an art exhibition that started out by inviting artists' contributions without anybody having seen the works first; 2. an exhibition with a catalog that will illustrate over 100 works—many of which will not be included in the show; 3. a catalog that lists artists that aren't represented in the show at all; 4. an exhibition that includes works that are not included....
(Continues...)


Excerpted from Systems We Have Loved by Eve Meltzer. Copyright © 2013 The University of Chicago. Excerpted by permission of THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Antepartum

1 The Dream of the Information World 2 Turning Around, Turning Away 3  The Expanded Field and Other, More Fragile States of Mind 4 After Words
Notes
Index
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews